A Big Bang Cosmological Argument for God's Nonexistence

Authors Avatar

I am a joint physics/ philosophy  student at Birmingham University, and this essay will come in useful to anyone studying the science of beliefs module, and similar related courses.

A Big Bang Cosmological Argument for God's Nonexistence

by Quentin Smith                              

The big bang cosmological theory is relevant to Christian theism and other theist perspectives since it represents the universe as beginning to exist ex nihilo about 15 billion years ago. This paper addresses the question of whether it is reasonable to believe that God created the big bang. Some theists answer in the affirmative, but it is argued in this paper that this belief is not reasonable. In the course of this argument, there is a discussion of the metaphysical necessity of natural laws, of whether the law of causality is true a priori, and of other pertinent issues.

1. Introduction

The advent of big bang cosmology in this century was a watershed for theists. Since the times of Copernicus and Darwin, many theists regarded science as hostile to their world-view and as requiring defence and retrenchment on the part of theism. But big bang cosmology in effect reversed this situation. The central idea of this cosmology, that the universe exploded into existence in a 'big bang' about 15 billion years ago or so, seemed tailor made to a theistic viewpoint. Big bang cosmology seemed to offer empirical evidence for the religious doctrine of creation ex nihilo. The theistic implications seemed so clear and exciting that even Pope Pius XII was led to comment that 'True science to an ever increasing degree discovers God as though God were waiting behind each door opened by science. But the theistic interpretation of the big bang has not only received widespread dissemination in popular culture and official sanction but also a sophisticated philosophical articulation. Richard Swinburne, John Leslie and especially William Lane Craig have developed powerful arguments for theism based on a well-grounded knowledge of the cosmological data and ideas.

The response of atheists and agnostics to this development has been comparatively weak, indeed, almost invisible. An uncomfortable silence seems to be the rule when the issue arises among nonbelievers or else the subject is briefly and epigrammatically dismissed with a comment to the effect that 'science has no relevance to religion.' The reason for the apparent embarrassment of nontheists is not hard to find. Anthony Kenny suggests it in this summary statement:

According to the big bang theory, the whole matter of the universe began to exist at a particular time in the remote past. A proponent of such a theory, at least if he is an atheist, must believe that the matter of the universe came from nothing and by nothing.

This idea disturbs many for the reason it disturbs C. D. Broad:

I must confess that I have a very great difficulty in supposing that there was a first phase in the world's history, i.e., a phase immediately before which there existed neither matter, nor minds, nor anything else. I suspect that my difficulty about a first event or phase in the world's history is due to the fact that, whatever I may say when I am trying to give Hume a run for his money, I cannot really believe in anything beginning to exist without being caused (in the old-fashioned sense of produced or generated) by something else which existed before and up to the moment when the entity in question began to exist. I find it impossible to give up the principle; and with that confession of the intellectual impotence of old age I must leave this topic.4

Motivated by concerns such as Broad's, some of the few nontheists who have been vocal on this subject have gone so far as to deny, without due justification, central tenets of big bang cosmology. Among physicists, the most notorious example is Fred Hoyle, who vehemently rejected the suggestion of a big bang that seemed to imply a Creator and unsuccessfully attempted to construe the evidence for a big bang as evidence for an evolving 'bubble' within a larger unchanging and infinitely old universe (I am referring to his 1970s post-steady-state theory5). An example of this contrary approach among philosophers is evinced by W. H. Newton-Smith. Newton-Smith felt himself compelled to maintain, in flat contradiction to the singularity theorems of big bang cosmology (which entail that there can be no earlier state of the universe than the big bang singularity) that the evidence that macroscopic events have causal origins gives us 'reason to suppose that some prior state of the universe led to the production of this particular singularity.'

It seems to me, however, that nontheists are not put in such dire straits by big bang cosmology. Nontheists are not faced only with the alternatives of embarrassed silence, confessions of impotence, epigrammatic dismissals or 'denial' when confronted with the apparently radical implications of big bang cosmology. It will be my purpose in this paper to show this by establishing a coherent and plausible atheistic interpretation of the big bang, an interpretation that is not only able to stand up to the theistic interpretation but is in fact better justified than the theistic interpretation. But my argument is intended to establish even more than this. I have elsewhere made the case that big bang cosmology does not lend support to theism but here I wish to make the stronger case that big bang cosmology is actually inconsistent with theism. I will argue that if big bang cosmology is true, then God does not exist.

The cosmological theory I shall discuss in this paper is the so-called 'standard hot big bang theory,' which is based on Friedmann's solutions to the equations of Einstein's General Theory of Relativity and the Hawking-Penrose singularity theorems. I shall explain these ideas in an introductory and nontechnical manner in section 2, so that philosophers who are unfamiliar with this theory may follow my argument. One point I wish to emphasize at the outset concerns the provisional status of the big bang theory. Cosmologists believe that this theory will one day be replaced by a cosmology based on a quantum theory of gravity and, consequently, theistic or atheistic conclusions that are derived from the 'standard hot big bang theory' must be treated with a similarly provisional status.

After my introductory explanation of big bang cosmology in section 2, I outline the 'big bang cosmological argument for God's nonexistence' in section 3. Most of the paper, sections 4-8, is devoted to responding to objections to the argument outlined in section 3.

2. The Big Bang Cosmological Theory

In this section the relevant aspects of the big bang theory are explained in four steps. These aspects will constitute the four scientific premises of the atheistic argument I shall construct in section 3.

(i) The first step is the introduction of the so-called 'Einstein equation,' which is the heart of Einstein's General Theory of Relativity.8 Einstein's equation says, in simplified terms, that the geometry (curvature) of spacetime is determined by the distribution of mass and energy in spacetime. The equation may be simplified as

(curvature of spacetime) = 8*pi*(density of matter).

This equation suggests that if the matter in the universe is sufficiently dense, then the curvature of spacetime will become so great that it eventually curves to a point, as at the tip of a cone. The history of a particle or light ray is a path in spacetime, and if spacetime eventually curves to a point then these spacetime paths will converge and intersect at the point. If this intersection occurs at some time in the future, the point of intersection would seem to constitute the end of spacetime. If the intersection occurs in the past, such that the spacetime paths emerge from the point of intersection and gradually curve away from each other, the point of intersection would appear to constitute the beginning of spacetime. This possibility leads to a discussion of the next relevant aspect of big bang cosmology.

(ii) Einstein's equation admits of many solutions and it is an empirical question which solution describes our universe. The Friedmann solutions (first obtained by Friedmann in 1922 and 19249) are the ones thought to apply to our universe. H is solution describe a universe that is perfectly isotropic (it looks the same in every direction) and perfectly homogeneous (matter is evenly distributed). If we apply to Einstein's equation a metric that describes a perfectly isotropic and homogeneous universe, the Friedmann solutions are obtained, which in a simplified form read

-3*(acceleration of expansion or deceleration of contraction of the universe) = 4*pi*(density of matter)

The Friedmann solutions tell us that if there is matter evenly distributed throughout the universe, then the universe must be expanding at a decreasing rate or contracting at an increasing rate (except at the instant, if any, at which the expansion stops and changes to a contraction). To see this, note that the right side of the above (simplified) equation represents the density of matter multiplied by 4*pi. If there is matter present in the universe, then the matter density of the universe is positive . This implies that the right side of the equation, 4*pi*(density of matter), will be positive. This in turn implies that the value for the acceleration of the expansion or the deceleration of the contraction will be negative. This is because the acceleration of the expansion or the deceleration of the contraction is multiplied by -3 and the result must be equal to the positive number represented by the right side of the equation. If the value of the expansion's acceleration is negative, this means that t he universe is expanding at an ever decreasing rate. If the value of the contraction's deceleration is negative, this means that the universe is contracting at an ever increasing rate. This result is of momentous significance, for it implies that if the universe contains evenly distributed matter then its existence is temporally limited. If the universe is contracting at an ever increasing rate, then it cannot contract forever but must eventually reach an endpoint, when it curves to a point and its radius becomes zero. If the universe is expanding at an ever decreasing rate, then it cannot have been expanding forever but must have begun expanding at some time in the past, when its radius began extending from zero.

Join now!

Let us further consider the case of expansion, since the universe is now expanding. The further we trace the universe into the past, the faster we find its rate of expansion. As the rate of expansion increases, the curvature of the universe and the density of matter increase and the radius of the universe decreases, until a time is reached when the curvature of the universe is infinite, the density of matter infinite and the radius of the universe is zero. Due to the infinite curvature, the past-directed spacetime paths of particles converge, such that each spacetime path ends at ...

This is a preview of the whole essay