Can We Justify Our Deductive Processes? I will begin by exploring the basic problem with deduction why it seems that any attempt to justify deduction is doomed to circularity, which would seem to make the task of constructing a valid justification im

Authors Avatar

Daniel Bregman        Can we Justify our Deductive Processes?        14 July 2011

Can we Justify our Deductive Processes?

by Daniel Bregman


Abstract

Logical deduction underpins almost all of our reasoning in philosophy and the wider world. In this essay I seek to answer the question of whether our deductive processes need justifying and, if so, how such a justification might be possible. The question has far-reaching consequences regarding the philosophical basis for most of our thought processes. I argue that a justification is impossible in the obvious sense of supporting our choice of deductive rules, but nevertheless our deductive reasoning is justified because it is made to correlate to our linguistic practice.

The initial problem is that it can be shown that justifying deduction will always involve deduction, and so such a justification will inevitably be circular. In addition, any method that seems to validate a given (valid) deductive inference will also validate a given (invalid) inference. However, I then show that circularity in arguments is not necessarily a damning property, through the use of examples both from logic and from science. By looking at the role of a proposed justification (explanatory rather than suasive) it seems that a justification of the sort initially examined may still be valid in some ways. In addition, the issue of how deductive reasoning is possible at all is linked to the concept of a theory of meaning, and of how we determine the conditions for the truth of a sentence.

Left with no reason to value one form of deduction above another, I then look at the possibilities that logic is empirical, conventional or pragmatic, with reference to several alternate logic systems. Having already established that any particular deductive reasoning may be justifiable in an explanatory extent, I contend that the only reason we can justify its use rather than any other logic’s is that the system of deduction and our linguistic practice are simultaneously brought into line with each other.

DANIEL BREGMAN

November 2009


Table of Contents

Can we Justify our Deductive Processes?        


Can we Justify our Deductive Processes?

1. Introduction

Deductive reasoning is something that we use constantly in our everyday lives, but in philosophy, and particularly its more analytic traditions, it takes on an even more important role, as the only way we have of moving from one line of argument to the next without a risk of error. Deduction is valued not just because it is a strong tool with which to take apart ideas and construct arguments, but also because it is truth-preserving – it should be impossible for the premises of a valid deductive argument to be true and the conclusion false. This means that we can use deductive arguments in philosophy to convince people of what we believe, because, as long as they agree with the starting premises, they cannot avoid agreeing with the conclusion.

Given that we use deductive reasoning so much, the philosophical issue arises of how we can justify it: how we can know that the rules we follow to construct deductive arguments really have the grounding to make them as strong as we want. If we cannot justify the processes we use, we must examine what allows us to use them anyway. In this essay I will examine how we might come to a justification of deduction, and what sort of justification we would consider to be an acceptable base for our reasoning. The scope of this essay will be confined to deductive processes, meaning both the rules for deductive inference but also the more general act of deductive reasoning – in other words, the way we make deductive arguments, and the fact that we can make them at all.

I will begin by exploring the basic problem with deduction – why it seems that any attempt to justify deduction is doomed to circularity, which would seem to make the task of constructing a valid justification impossible. However, I will then move onto a proposal that could make some types of circular reasoning acceptable, based on what the justification is meant to achieve. I will also describe the details of a deductive system in more detail, to show how there are several different aspects that a justification could address, to justify not just the rules of inference but the theory of meaning behind them. Lastly, I will examine alternate possibilities for the basis of our logic, including the possibility that logic is empirical, or made by convention. The fact that some philosophers today advocate alternate forms of logic also has implications for the question of justification.

         2. The Problem with Deduction

A famous problem with inductive reasoning was articulated by David Hume, who recognised that the main justification for induction seems to be that it works; in other words:

A1        (1) The rule of induction has worked well in the past.

         The rule of induction will work well in the future.

This argument, however, is itself an inductive argument, and so the justification is circular – it presupposes that we accept inductive reasoning, and will therefore accept the argument in favour of inductive reasoning. A similar example occurs for deductive reasoning, because any attempt to apply a general rule to a specific instance will inevitably involve some kind of deductive reasoning. This can be illustrated by examining an attempt to justify a basic deductive argument. For example, the following is an example of the deductive rule modus ponendo ponens (MPP):

A2        (1) If A, then B

        (2) A

         B

There are two ways in which a single deductive inference such as this can be defined: syntactically or semantically. The syntactic definition takes the form of rules which show what ‘steps’ we can make from premise to conclusion, and the semantic definition takes the form of truth tables which prevent the possibility of true premises and false conclusion. Similarly, there are two ways of describing deductive arguments as a whole. Syntactically, a deductive argument is a series of statements which proceed to a conclusion in accordance with the rules for inference. Semantically, it is a series of statements and a conclusion such it cannot be the case that the premises are true and the conclusion false. To establish a logical theory logicians formalise these two approaches and try to demonstrate two things: firstly, that if the syntactic relation holds, so does the semantic (this is a soundness theorem), and secondly that if the semantic relation holds, so does the syntactic (a completeness theorem). The soundness theorem is a necessity; the completeness theorem is desired, but less crucial. For a single inference:

Join now!

        MPP        From: A  B, A

                To infer: B                (syntactic definition)

                (semantic definition)

An attempt could be made to justify the above argument by either definition. The justification would, however, take the form:

A3        (1) If ‘if A, then B’ and ‘A’ are true, ‘B’ is true

        (2) ‘if A, then B’ and ‘A’ are true

         ‘B’ is true

This argument, however, takes exactly the same form as the original argument, and so in order to accept it we must accept the validity of MPP. But this was exactly what we ...

This is a preview of the whole essay