May 12, 2010

The Categorical Imperative and its Shortcomings

When you are in a given situation in which you need to make moral judgment, how do you come to decide what is morally correct? Two popular tests used to make such decision question the consistency, and fairness of the situation at hand. However, these two tests leave much to be desired. Immanuel Kant provides a better procedure for one to evaluate one’s moral actions. For Kant, moral requirements are categorical imperatives, and he introduces two tests in order to decide what a morally acceptable action is. The first test says that actions are morally acceptable only when the principles that inspire them can be acted on by everybody, and the second requires us to treat humanity as an end and never as a means. Categorical imperatives are considered inescapable on non-moral grounds. Nevertheless, Kant’s categorical imperatives as the ultimate principle of morality leave much to be desired, and although at first may seem extremely sophisticated, the principle is too simple to make much more moral advancement.

The first of two popular tests of consistency and fairness involves asking the question: what if everyone did that? The real problem with this test, apart from the fact that it sometimes delivers mistaken verdicts, is that it makes the morality of an action depend on how it is described (Shafer-Landau 145). The second popular test is the golden rule which relies on the question: how would you like it if I did that to you? It is an unreliable test of morality because it makes morality depend on a person’s desire, which cannot be controlled. The golden rule also fails to give us actual guidance on self-regarding actions. Because the above tests sometimes give the wrong answer to moral questions, neither can be the ultimate test of morality (Shafer-Landau 146). 

Kant’s goal was to identify the ultimate principle of morality which would explain the attraction of the two previously mentioned tests and at the same time correct their limitations. Since according to Kant, morality is about the things one can control, he introduces maxims—the actions one controls, and thus the type of actions one can be held accountable for. When moral reasons apply to a situation they are always the strongest reasons, since they defeat the importance of any other consideration. If morality requires one to do something, then it is what one must do even if one does not want to. When one acts immorally, one acts irrationally because one would be acting contrary to moral reasons.

Join now!

For Kant, the question of what is “right” comes prior to the question of what is good. Talent and ability is good if put to good use, but it can also be bad. Let’s consider the following example: hackers have the expertise to use computer technology to create “viruses” and cause fraudulent attacks. On the other hand, those that fight such hackers, are also hackers who have the same type of knowledge but choose to instead fight the immoral hackers. Because of this, only one thing is good in and of itself unconditionally, and that is a good "will" which means the will of ...

This is a preview of the whole essay