Our shared humanity and place in society demand that we should be more responsible for the well being of our fellows than is suggested by the current narrow scope of liabilities for omissions under the Law of England and Wales. (Anon., 2010

Authors Avatar

ADVANCED CRIMINAL LAW ESSAY

‘Our shared humanity and place in society demand that we should be more responsible for the well being of our fellows than is suggested by the current narrow scope of liabilities for omissions under the Law of England and Wales.’ (Anon., 2010)


Discuss.

 
The p recounts a Jewish man being robbed, beaten and left for dead on the side of the road. A priest and a Levite - Jews in good standing, pass him by. A third man - a Samaritan despised by Jews, gives aid to the man.  As compelling as it may be that such should be the norm, the law under England and Wales generally only attributes blame and liability for actions that cause harm and does not actively require benevolence between man and man. An exception to this exists under the narrow scope of liabilities for omissions at common law whereby there are certain circumstances where a failure to act when there is a duty to act will be criminal. Other jurisdictions impose ‘Bad Samaritan’ statutes on individuals to render assistance to those in peril and there are contrasting opinions as to whether or not England and Wales should adopt a similar stance. The aim of this essay is to discuss the circumstances in which the common law attaches liability for omissions and to discern whether or not the scope of liability for omissions should be extended to include a general duty, because at present, it is up to moral consciousness of individuals whether or not they choose to be a Good Samaritan.

THE SCOPE OF OMISSIONS LIABILITY

The Common Law under England and Wales recognises that criminal liability for omissions will only arise when there is a duty to act. It has been suggested that it is not entirely certain when a duty to act will arise  nevertheless, it is accepted that the following situations will prima face give rise to a duty to act;  where there is a special relationship, where responsibility has been assumed, where a duty has been assumed by contract and where the defendant has created a dangerous situation.

Norrie suggests that the development of the modern approach to omissions liability under the Law of England and Wales is embedded in the 19th Century laissez-faire approach where the juridical basis for a duty to act was characterised by a strict contractual nexus. A depiction of this contractual correlation can be found in the cases of R v Instan [1893]  and more evidently in R v Pittwood [1902].  In Instan the niece’s duty was discussed in broadly moral terms but the core of her responsibility for failing to act and look after her aunt was deemed to be because the aunt paid for the house and provided money to the niece for her and her niece’s upkeep. This agreement gave rise to an implied contract between the aunt and her niece which was broken when the niece failed to care for her.  In Pittwood even though the contract was between Pittwood and his employer; the court approached it and read in an implicit contract between Pitwood and the people who would be hurt if he did not stick to the terms of his employment.  This strict approach has created problems when attempting to attach liability in morally inexcusable situations whereby contractual elements are not as evident; this is well illustrated in Stone & Dobinson [1977].  Two arguments were raised in order to attach criminal liability to the omissions of the defendants, thus being; the blood relationship between Stone and the deceased and the undertaking of care for the deceased by both defendants. Williams articulates that ‘there was a slide in the judgement between 'undertaking' in a practical and in a 'contractual' sense.’ In order to find liability the judges were forced to construe the contractualist approach to fit to the facts of the case. The use of a contractual model arguably narrows the scope for liability and establishes that the existence of a duty to act only where a previous commitment has been voluntarily undertaken. This doctrine was however slightly widened by the decision in R v Miller [1983] and there is mixed academic opinion as to how liability was found in this case. Williams advocates for the 'continuing act' theory and that the whole course of conduct of the defendant should be viewed as one uninterrupted Actus Reus, thus liability was found for a positive act rather than for an omission. Smith claims that the harm is caused by the omission to take steps to avert the harm. Norrie argues that there was still a free undertaking and that liability was found under a contractual interpretation.

Join now!


RECOGNISING BAD SAMARITAN LAWS 

It is manifested in the Common Law that the law as it stands under England and Wales is narrow and largely restricted by archaic laissez-faire principles. To circumvent this ideology the law under England and Wales could follow in the footsteps of those countries that are more interventionalist and impose a general duty to act to those in peril; notably France and Germany where ‘Bad Samaritan’ laws are enforced. As defined by Malm, Bad Samaritan laws are ‘laws that oblige persons, on pain of criminal punishment, to provide easy rescues and other acts of aid for ...

This is a preview of the whole essay