Consideration is therefore historically a fundamental doctrine of English law and has equally been the subject of much criticism owing to its rigidity and lack of coherence.

Authors Avatar by megankhong (student)

The classic model of English Contract law is a bargain and a bargain postulates an exchange. In his much respected work, Sir Frederick Pollock rightfully explained that "[a]n act or forbearance of one party, or the promise thereof, is the price for which the promise of the other is bought, and the promise thus given for value is enforceable." Consideration is therefore historically a fundamental doctrine of English law and has equally been the subject of much criticism owing to its rigidity and lack of coherence. Lord Steyn raised an important question as to why should the law refuse to sanction a transaction for want of consideration where parties seriously intend to enter into legal relations and arrive at a concluded agreement? A major failing of the bargain theory, it is said, is that it excludes detrimental reliance as a basis for enforcing a promise but allows for an executory promise to constitute consideration. One good example is the controversial case of Stilk and Myrick. Accordingly, attempts have been made to circumvent the rigors of the doctrine using equitable principles which shifts the conceptual focus away from the notion of exchange to that of reliance to give effect to the reasonable expectations of parties or by taking into account whether the parties intended to be bound in the first place.

The stage is now set for an analysis of the sweeping statement made by Lord Denning in his judgement in Combe v Combe. In Combe’s case a husband promised to pay his wife an annual amount for maintenance prior to a divorce but failed to do so when the divorce was realised. There was no consideration, but the wife tried to bring an action against her husband on the basis of promissory estoppel. The first instance judgement was overturned by the aforesaid judge on the basis that the principle in High Trees case (which was applied by Bryne J in an earlier court) may be part of a cause of action, but not a cause of action in itself and thus could not be applied where there was no pre-existing contractual duty. In obiter, the learned judge reaffirmed the position of the doctrine as so deeply entrenched in the common law tradition to be displaced by ‘a side wind’ which was in this case, the doctrine of promissory estoppel.

It would not do justice to omit from our analysis the radical proposal for reforms brought about in the Law Revision Committee’s Sixth Interim Report. In proposing the eradication of some of the most venerable flaws in the law of contract, the committee declared that “enough has been said to show that to-day in very many cases the doctrine of consideration is a mere technicality, which is irreconcilable either with business expediency or common sense, and that it frequently affords a man a loophole for escape from a promise which he has deliberately given with intent to create a binding obligation and in reliance on which the promisee may have acted.” However, the proposals were never implemented and it’s not hard to see why.

Francis Bennion asserted in his work that the suggestion that it is open for the courts to uproot a doctrine so firmly embedded in the common law could only be at the cost of incalculable damage to a far more important principle, that of stare decisis. Yet, academicians have argued that the courts have not always applied the doctrine in a rigid manner. Atiyah was of the view that consideration was originally understood as a good reason (causa in Roman law) for enforcing or not enforcing promises. It wasn’t until the nineteenth century that it formalised to a set of rules which was founded upon the doctrine of reciprocity. However, the courts applied it only to situations they deemed worthy of enforcement such as promises contrary to public policy, promises made in the social and domestic sphere and bargains procured by duress or extortion, in effect, assuming a paternalistic role. This shows that the courts may have never intended the doctrine of consideration to result in an overly technical and archaic set of rules and in the consequent loss of sight of the practical reasons for the doctrine in the first place, viz, distinguishing seriously intended and gratuitous promises.

Join now!

In 1952, a year subsequent to Combe’s case, Denning LJ wrote an article in The Modern Law Review where he addressed the distinction between a promise given in formation of a contract and a promise given in discharge of a contract. There he quoted Sir Frederick Pollock: “The doctrine of consideration has been extended, with not very happy results, beyond its proper scope, which is to govern the formation of contracts, and has been made to regulate and restrain the discharge of contracts.” Consequently he wrote, “If one compares the cases concerning promises on the formation of a contract, with those concerning ...

This is a preview of the whole essay