The command theory's black and white distinction between law and moralty - a weekness in legal positivism generally?

Authors Avatar

JURISPRUDENCE

YEAR 2 ASSESSED ESSAY

THE COMMAND THEORY’S BLACK AND WHITE DISTINCTION BETWEEN LAW AND MORALITY: A WEAKNESS IN LEGAL POSITIVISM GENERALLY?

Question 6 

Fuller writes of Austin: “Over and over again he teeters on the edge of an abandonment of the command theory… Yet he never takes the plunge. He does not take it because he had a sure insight that it would forfeit the black-and-white distinction between law and morality that was the whole object of his Lectures…” (Lon L. Fuller, “Positivism and Fidelity to Law – A Reply to Professor Hart” (1958) 71 Harv. L. Rev. 630, p 640). Does this comment identify a weakness in legal positivism generally?

Student ID: 316553

December 2001 / January 2002


“Everything’s got a moral, if you can only find it”, wrote Lewis Carroll. Alice has a sure insight into the beliefs of natural lawyers, but to many positivists she is operating in a wonderland. Morality, according to positivist theories, is distinguished from questions of law. Many argue, however, that this overlooks the fundamental foundations of legal systems and legal validity, which are based not just on law but also on morality. To assess the accuracy of this statement it is necessary to consider whether positivism does indeed create a “black and white distinction” between law and morality, and whether such a distinction should be regarded as a weakness.

I will focus on the views of notable positivists and the contrasting theories of natural lawyers. It is the debate and counter-debate of these jurisprudential camps that has provided the most thorough arguments for and against the proposition that positivism is weakened by its separation of law and morals.

The founder of English positivism, Jeremy Bentham, developed the command theory of law with central concepts of sovereign, command and sanction. It is an imperative theory that emphasises the coercive element of the law, and defines law in terms of facts: “the political facts of power, human prescriptions, punishments and rewards”. It is this that allows the formulation of “a scientific theory of legislation based on the principle of utility”. Utilitarianism is the principle of maximisation of pleasure and the minimisation of pain, but it does not involve moral judgements. According to Bentham, law should be investigated only in terms of factual issues.

This is the framework from which John Austin derived his own jurisprudential model. His 1832 publication, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, is generally cited as the definitive exposition of the command theory of law. Like Bentham, Austin extracted and adapted the traditional political philosophies of Bodin and Hobbes, which explained sources of authority and obligation in terms of “the command of a sovereign backed by a sanction”. Austin did not see a sovereign as having a divine or natural right to tell us what we ought to do: the sovereign was identified purely “by the fact that he was obeyed”, and his commands were identified by the people as “laws”.

By this definition, law is made by the supreme legislative body (government) or institutions acting under the Government’s directions. It is the source of the law by which its legality can be determined. The criteria for legality are therefore matters not of substantive merit, morality or value, but of objectivity and fact. This is the “black-and-white distinction between law and morality” which Austin asserted in his lectures. This separation is fundamental to the command theory’s premise that all laws are commands backed by threats, and without the distinction, it is argued, the theory would destabilize.

Fuller is therefore correct in saying that there is a rigid separation of law and morals in Austinianism. Can the same be said for all positivism? Most positivists, such as Hans Kelsen, believe that the inclusion of value judgements, such as moral factors, is a weakness of natural law arguments. One line of reasoning is that value judgements are purely subjective, and “therefore, cannot be admitted into the scientific study of law as… objective phenomen[a]”. It is also argued by positivists that naturalist theories wrongly confuse what law ‘is’ and what law ‘ought to be’ by incorporating moral and ethical criteria into an identification of law. H.L.A. Hart’s positivist revival theory shares this belief, and he contends that it is a reason why naturalist theories should be rejected.

Join now!

On closer inspection, however, it becomes clear that Hart’s views are different from those of Austin. In fact, Hart critiqued almost every aspect of Austin’s theory. He believes that the coercive expression of political power, implicit within the theory, fails to sufficiently account for the character of law as a social, obligation-imposing, phenomenon. Many others have criticised Austin’s command model, to the extent that “there are few, if any, at the present day, who regard him as either wholly successful in this undertaking or as being altogether clear-minded in his basic aims”. It is clear evidence that Austin’s so ...

This is a preview of the whole essay