The Two Judgments: Golaknath and Kesavananda Bharati - The purpose of this article is not to criticize the judgment, but to give its effect and the changes it made in the previous constitutional position of fundamental rights.

Authors Avatar

The Two Judgments: Golaknath and Kesavananda Bharati
by K. Subba Rao (Ex-Chief Justice of India)

Cite as : (1973) 2 SCC (Jour) 1


The purpose of this article is not to criticize the judgment, but to give its effect and the changes it made in the previous constitutional position of fundamental rights.

Before considering the effect of the recent judgment, it would be convenient at this stage to notice the scope of Golaknath judgment for two reasons: (1) there is misapprehension as regards the scope of the said decision and (2) it would help to ascertain how far and to what extent, the fundamental freedoms of the people, as recognised by that decision, have been changed by the recent decision.

In that case the landlord questioned the constitutional validity of an Act passed by the legislature taking away the fundamental rights in an estate. The Supreme Court dismissed the petition of the landlord. That is to say, contrary to the impression created by propaganda, the rich man lost the case. In effect it laid down the following propositions:

(1) All the amendments made up to the date the judgment was delivered, were valid.

(2) The amendment under Article 368 being law, it is subject to the provisions of Article 13 and therefore if the said law takes away or abridges the fundamental rights, except in the manner and to the extend prescribed by Part III, it will be void.

(3) Parliament can, by the law of amendment or by ordinary law, abridge or restrict the fundamental rights to the extent permitted in Part III.

(4) Though it cannot take away the fundamental rights, it can add to the list of fundamental rights.

It will be seen from the said propositions that the Supreme Court, as wrongly represented, did not hold that Parliament has no power to amend fundamental rights. On the other hand it held that it could amend all the fundamental rights, but it could not, by the process of amendment, take away the fundamental rights or restrict them beyond that sanctioned by Part III. It follows that under the decision the Parliament can add to the list of fundamental rights or restrict them reasonably in public interest. To put it in other words, Parliament cannot by amendment take away, to use the terminology of the recent Supreme Court Judgment, the core of the fundamental rights.

In that case, before the Supreme Court two alternative arguments were advanced: (1) As Article 368 is subject to Article 13, any law of amendment taking away or abridging the fundamental rights beyond that prescribed under Part III would be void, and (2) In exercise of its power of amendment, Parliament cannot destroy the basic structure of the Constitution, but it can only modify the provisions thereof within the framework of the original instrument for its better effectuation; and the fundamental rights formed part of the basic structure. The Supreme Court accepted the first argument and held that whether the law of amendment was made in exercise of the power under Article 248 or of the power implied in Article 368, it being 'law' would be void if it was made in contravention of the provisions of Article 13. On the second question the Supreme Court held that there was considerable force, but it did not express its final opinion thereon as the case before it could be decided on the first point.

The criticism of the Golaknath Judgment ran on the following lines.

(1) It was held in the Judgment that the Parliament has no power to amend the Constitution in order to abridge the fundamental rights.

(2) It was held therein that the power to amend the Constitution was conferred on the Parliament under Articles 245, 248 and entry 97 of Schedule I, that Article 368 only prescribed the procedure and therefore any law amending the Constitution taking away or abridging the fundamental rights would be void in terms of Article 13 of the Constitution. The said legal position, it was said, was erroneous as the power to amend was a constituent power conferred on the Parliament under Article 368 and therefore any law made in exercise of that power would not be hit by Article 13 which only governed laws made in exercise of legislative power.

(3) The Judgment had so entrenched the right to property that it stood in the way of the Parliament in improving the socio-economic conditions of the country.

The first ground of criticism has no basis. The Supreme Court of India in Golaknath Judgment did not say that the Parliament has no power to abridge the fundamental rights. What it said was it has no power to abridge the fundamental rights except in the manner and to the extent prescribed in Part III of the Constitution. To put in other words, as the amendment is "law" within the meaning of Part III of the Constitution, Parliament can restrict the fundamental rights in accordance with the relevant provisions of Part III. In effect it said Parliament cannot by amendment take away the core of the fundamental rights.

The broad sweep of the power of the Parliament to restrict or limit the fundamental rights in order to implement the directive principles will be apparent if the relevant provisions of Part III are scrutinised. The fundamental right to equality is subject to the law of acquisition; the right to admission to colleges and employment is subject to the law making special provision for backward communities and scheduled castes; the right to seven freedoms is subject to the laws of reasonable restrictions in public interest; the right to life and personal liberty is subject to procedure prescribed by law; the right to property is subject to the law of deprivation, acquisition and taxation; the right against exploitation is subject to the law of imposing compulsory services for public purpose; the right to freedom of religion is subject to laws of public order, morality and health and also the law regulating or restricting economic, financial, political or other secular activity or provisions for social welfare and reform; the right to manage religious affairs is subject to the law of public order, morality; and the right to administer the property of religious institutions is subject to law. The fundamental rights can also be modified by Parliament by law in their application to armed forces and the forces charged with the maintenance of the public order. They may also be restricted by Parliament by law while martial law is in force and when the proclamation of emergency is issued during the continuance of which, Article 19 is suspended and the President by special order can suspend other rights. A scrutiny of the said provisions discloses that the Parliament has ample power to make laws in public interest to restrict the said rights. To put it in other words, while the Parliament has the necessary power to make laws restricting the said fundamental rights reasonably in public interest, the Constitution has provided for a minimal judicial check against the autocratic exercise of that power. This minimal check on autocracy is irksome to men in power.

The second criticism is also not sound. It is true that five of the six judges who formed the majority held that amendment is law within the meaning of Article 248 of the Constitution and that Article 368 only lays down the procedure. But the sixth judge found that power in Article 368 itself. It is immaterial whether the power to amend the Constitution is found in one provision or other, for it is a power under the Constitution. It is also immaterial whether the said power is called legislative power, amending power or constituent power, so long the amendment made in exercise of the said power is law. If it is law, Article 13 is automatically attracted. That apart, the criticism mixes up the two concepts of amending power and constituent power. It may be that the amending power is carved out of the constituent power. It may also be that the amending power may loosely be described as constituent power. But the distinction between the two is real. One is a power outside the Constitution and inherent in the people. The other is a power under the Constitution which vests in the Parliament. Therefore, any amendment made in exercise of the power under the Constitution is "law" within the wide meaning of the definition of Article 13. The result of the said decision, whatever may be the reasoning thereunder, was that the Parliament by amendment cannot take away the fundamental rights but can abridge them within the limits laid down by Part III. It can even add other fundamental rights to the list.

The third ground is an alibi for incompetence or neglect of duty. To appreciate the scope of the judgment in the context of its effect on the right to property, it would be necessary to know the scope of the said right as it existed before the said judgment.

The then constitutional position of the right to property may be briefly stated thus:

1. Every citizen has a fundamental right to acquire, hold and dispose of property;

2. The State can make a law imposing reasonable restrictions on the said right in public interest. The said restrictions, under certain circumstances, may amount even to deprivation of the said right;

3. Whether a restriction imposed by law on a fundamental right is reasonable and in public interest or not is a justiciable issue;

4. The State can, by law, deprive a person of his property if the said law of deprivation amounts to a reasonable restriction in public interest within the meaning of Article 19(5);

5. The State can acquire or requisition the property of a person for a public purpose after paying compensation;

6. The adequacy of the compensation is not justiciable;

7. If the compensation fixed by law is illusory or is contrary to the principles relevant to the fixation of compensation, it would be a fraud on power and, therefore, the validity of such a law becomes justiciable; and

8. Laws of agrarian reform depriving or restricting the rights in an estate — the said expression has been defined to include practically every land in a village — cannot be questioned on the ground that they have infringed fundamental rights;

9. The State has powers to impose taxes on all types of property and incomes.

The result is that in India the State has ample power to make laws to bring about all agrarian reforms unhampered by fundamental rights. The State had now become the final authority in the shaping of land tenures.

Even on industrial and business front the Constitution has conferred large powers on the State to regulate it, to prevent concentration of wealth and exploitation and even to nationalise an industry or business in public interest.

Briefly stated, before the Golaknath judgment there was practically no fundamental right to property in regard to an estate, which by definition includes almost all the land in rural area. In regard to other property the State can tax it. If acquired, it has to pay compensation to its owner on relevant principles, and which is not illusory. The slogan which, by repetition has become a conviction in the uninformed mind that under the Indian Constitution the property right has become entrenched, has therefore no foundation in fact. What the judgment in effect saved were other fundamental rights such as right to equality, seven freedoms, right against exploitation, right to life and liberty, etc. from total extinction.

The Parliament passed the 24th Amendment with the object of overruling the effect of Golaknath judgment and to assert the Parliament's power to take away the fundamental rights. The 25th, 26th and 29th Amendments to the Constitution were made abridging the fundamental rights in certain areas or in respect of certain laws. The question of the validity of the said Amendments was the subject-matter of the recent Supreme Court judgment in Kesavananda Bharat v. State of Kerala, (1973) 4 SCC 225. It was heard by 13 Judges. All the Judges unanimously held that the 24th Amendment is valid and in exercise of its power conferred thereunder Parliament can amend any Article of the Constitution including the fundamental rights. But seven of the Judges held that the Parliament by amendment of the Constitution cannot affect the basic structure of the Constitution. There is conflict on the question of the content of the structure and whether and to what extent and in what circumstances the fundamental rights form part of the said structure.

The effect of the judgment depends upon the content of the expression 'basic structure of the Constitution'. The basic structure of the Constitution takes in, not only the institutions but also the fundamental principles or the objectives of the Constitution. If the latter are ignored, the former will become a body without a soul, for the structure is so designed as to implement the philosophy of the Constitution. Indeed, the philosophy and the institutional devices are so mixed up that if they are separated it becomes a different Constitution. The Constitution in sonorous terms resolved to constitute India as a Sovereign Democratic Republic and to secure to all its citizens Justice, Liberty, Equality and Fraternity. The Preamble is not a platitude. It is the condensed version of its philosophy. It is sought to be implemented through the provisions of the Constitution.

The basic structure of the Constitution is made up of the following concepts:

1. Republic: Republic is an independent, sovereign power or State. It is distinguished from monarchy or oligarchy. The power vests in the people. It is a State in which the supremacy of the people is formally acknowledged. It is a Government for the protection of the citizens against the exercise of arbitrary and unjust power.

2. Democracy: Democracy is a form of Government where people exercise their power to take political decisions through their representatives selected by the process of free election. It is a representative and responsible Government. The fundamentals of democracy are free elections and freedoms. Both go together; one cannot exist without the other. If people are deprived of their freedoms, there cannot be free elections. The Government so elected, in order to perpetuate itself, will supress the freedoms of the people. So the basis of democracy is freedoms. They are preserved and protected by conventions in highly-developed democracies, where there are no written Constitutions; they are embodied and protected under written Constitutions in their Democracies; they are described as Bill or rights in some Constitutions and as fundamental rights in others. Another aspect of the concept of freedom is the equality of all men, for democratic freedom necessarily means freedom for all people, which means the abolition of glaring inequalities. There may be additions or restrictions or even suspension of fundamental rights, having regard to time, place and circumstances, but without them democracy will be a caricature or empty shell.

3. Constitutional Democracy: It is an evolved device to control the tremendous economic and political power the executive, over the years, has gathered into its hands. The essence of Constitutional Democracy is the existence of an effective restraint upon political and governmental action. By definition it is a limited Government or a Government that is subject to restraints. In Constitutional Democracy the Constitution is supreme and all the institutions created thereunder shall function within the limits laid down therein. The existence of rights is an important substantive check on the Government; judicial review makes the check real, for it is the machinery to enforce the rights. Indeed, the means is a part of the right and therefore the judicial review is itself made a fundamental right.

Join now!

4. Federation: Federation is a form of Government wherein the sovereign power is divided between the Centre and the States.

5. Welfare State: Welfare State is a compromise between capitalism and communism. It has taken the good points of both and avoided their defects. In a Welfare State the people have freedoms. But the said freedoms are regulated by the State through laws and the arbitrary power of the State is controlled by judiciary. Part III and Part IV represent the core of the Indian Constitutional philosophy. Part III enshrines the fundamental rights and Part IV declares the directive ...

This is a preview of the whole essay