Nietzsche and Mill on Conventional Morality

Authors Avatar

Compare Contrast and Evaluate Nietzsche and Mill on Conventional Morality

At the time Nietzsche and Mill were writing conventional morality was, and arguably still is today, Christian morality, best summarised as Kant’s Deontological Ethics. Interestingly both of the two Philosophers take a similar stance towards this view of morality. They are both concerned that it’s uniform approach leads to a stagnation of ideas, what Mill refers to as an “unthinking mediocrity” and Nietzsche calls “a herd morality”. However they offer radically different alternatives, Nietzsche’s assessment of the ‘herd morality’ develops into him championing ‘Master Morality’, whereas Mill’s assessment develops into his liberal utilitarianism. These alternatives come about from the subtle differences in their assessments as to why these problems evolve, and it is through looking at how their alternative moral codes developed from their views on conventional morality that we can get the best illustration of how their views differ.

 It could be seen that Nietzsche’s development from his criticism of conventional morality is more logical, in the sense that his morality is a logical evolution of his assessment, yet we must accept that – on the surface at least - society seems to hold closer Mill’s ideals. One example of how Nietzsche seems to have the more logical approach would be Mill’s justification of why happiness is desirable, he says simply “that people desire it”. The first problem with this is that to say that something is desired does not justify that something should be desired, (for example I may desire a cigarette, yet to have one would be detrimental to my health and the health of those around me – perhaps not so desirable after all!) a line of reasoning that Bertrand Russell described as “so fallacious that it is hard to understand how he could have thought it valid”. However, let us take it as a strong, sound, altogether brilliant piece of logic for a minute. Whilst it is true that I desire my own happiness, and quite plausibly the happiness of those around me and those I hold close to me, to say that I desire the happiness of someone I have never met, and further more am not even aware of the existence of seems impossible. However the argument that people desire happiness and so happiness is desirable could be used with some strength to justify Nietzsche’s Egoism if we take the feeling of happiness to be a by-product of the affirmation of the will. Of course, the point Mill is trying to illustrate is that if people desire happiness then happiness is desirable, and so as a collective we should aim to maximise this. The problem he has is that seemingly at no point does he justify this collective idealism.

Mill differs from the view of Conventional Morality only on how the value of an action should be judged, not really on the course of action that should be taken, however he rightly recognised the huge implications of this seemingly minor difference. The difference lies in the differentiation between the value of the action and the level of blame/credit given to the person committing that action. Mill’s Utilitarianism would advocate almost exactly the same course of action as Conventional Morality in most situations. As a Rule Utilitarian he would rule out the taking of human life on the basis that it would rarely be conducive to overall happiness, he would also agree that theft and adultery are undesirable, and would probably agree with more or less all of the Christian moral code. The difference comes in why these actions should be ascribed a value. Conventional Morality would dictate that these actions were in themselves ‘good’ or ‘bad’, and that the value of them lies in the action itself, whereas Mill’s Utilitarianism argues that the value of the action is in the consequences that action has. So in the case of someone giving money to a charity, Conventional Morality would advocate this as a good action because it demonstrates the ‘virtue’ (in the non-Aristotelian sense of the word) of generosity. Mill’s Utilitarianism would also advocate this, but because the consequences would probably result in a greater aggregate happiness, rather than because the action itself was intrinsically good or because it demonstrated an intrinsically good personal quality.

However whilst Mill judges the value of the action itself differently to a conventional moralist, it is a mistake to think he would judge the person committing the action any differently. Mill writes, “Actions should be judged according to their probable consequences regardless of any religious codes or binding principles.” The implication of which is that a person should be judged on their intentions in committing an action in exactly the same way as they would be in a conventional moral system. In order for you to intend to do something, you must first be aware of the likely effect an action will have so that you can chose which action will have the closest outcome to your intention. Likewise, in order to judge a possible action according to its ‘probable consequences’ you must first have an ideal you wish to achieve, an intention.

Join now!

It is in the differentiation of the judgement of the action itself and the person committing the action that Mill’s morality stems from. This differs from conventional morality, as by judging the action itself as good or bad, and the person committing the action on their intent to commit the action, conventional morality may only have two moral classifications – good, or bad. Whereas Mill, by judging the action according to its consequences, and the person committing the action on what they may reasonably have believed the ‘probable consequences’ were is left with a classification by varying shades of ...

This is a preview of the whole essay