'An analysis of arguments for the existence of God will result in valid philosophical reasons to believe in God.' Discuss and assess this claim

Authors Avatar

Julia Wilson

An analysis of arguments for the existence of God will result in valid philosophical reasons to believe in God.’ Discuss and assess this claim with reference to the following two arguments for the existence of God:
(i) Religious Experience

(ii) Ontological Argument

I will first discuss the Ontological Argument for the existence of God, most famously expounded by Anselm, the Archbishop of Canterbury, in 1078. He wrote in The Proslogion that he considered the existence of God to be logically necessary. His reasoning, unlike that for the Teleological Argument and the Cosmological Argument, is a priori because it does not rely on experience from the world around us or on the evidence of our own senses. It is deductive, because the conclusion is contained within the premises, and analytic, because it is supposedly true by definition alone. All other versions of this argument are generally considered to be restatements of Anselm’s.

The simplest form of the argument states that if we were to meditate on the concept of God, it would become self evidently obvious that He exists. The more developed argument attempts to use the essence of the nature of God to prove His existence. Anselm reasoned that any being we could call ‘God’ must be that reality than which no more perfect can be conceived: his logic hinges upon this definition. J N Findlay, a contemporary philosopher, justifies his view: ‘we are led on irresistibly to demand that our religious object should have an unsurpassable supremacy along all avenues…the proper object of reverence should be all-comprehensive.’ The idea is that God cannot just happen to exist, nor something on which all other objects just happen to depend. He must be something that could not not exist, and on which objects could not not depend. He must not merely be one to which no actual independent realities stand opposed, He must be one to which such opposition is totally inconceivable. He must cover the territory of the possible as well as that of the actual. The existence of other things must be unthinkable without Him, and most importantly His own non-existence must be ‘wholly unthinkable’ in any circumstances. There must, in short, be no conceivable alternative to God. This leads to the notion of a being in whom essence and existence lose their separateness.

Given this concept of God, Anselm followed what he thought was a logical step to conclude that it would be incoherent and self-contradictory to think of such a being not existing, because a non-existent deity would not be that than which none greater can be conceived. Anselm tried to demonstrate the truth of his argument by reducing to absurdity the very opposite of what he was trying to prove. A crucial step in his argument was to judge existence as a perfection – something that can be lacked or possessed by a being or thing, and which contributes to our understanding of the nature of that thing – comparable to goodness, wisdom, or love. He therefore treats it as a predicate (a defining characteristic). Existence may be possessed or lacked, and it may be possessed in re or in intellectu. To possess it is necessarily greater than to lack it. Therefore, that which only possesses it in the mind, despite possibly having other qualities that make it great, can never be as great as that which possesses in reality. Relying heavily on the Principle of Conceivability, Anselm claimed that we could in theory conceive of another God, exactly the same as the first, except that this one exists. This would automatically make Him greater. But there cannot ever be something greater than God: Anselm accordingly reasoned that a God only possessing existence in intellectu could not exist. God, He than which nothing greater can be conceived, must possess existence in both senses. Otherwise, something greater than Him would be conceivable. So, when faced with the fact that people do claim what he thinks impossible (that God does not exist) Anselm cites psalm 53 – ‘the fool has said in his heart there is no God.’ After having attempted to reduce the atheist’s argument to absurdity, Anselm suggests the atheist does not understand the full implications of the concept of God. Had the atheist grasped the real meaning of God, as that which nothing greater can be conceived, he would realise that it is logically impossible for God not to exist – ‘no-one who understands what God is can think that God does not exist.’

Join now!

Rene Descartes was also a supporter of the Ontological Argument, focusing specifically on God’s necessary existence. He reasoned that God was a supremely perfect being, and therefore had all perfections. He assumed, as Anselm had done, that existence was a perfection. God, therefore, would have the perfection of existence and it is impossible to think of God as not having it. God cannot not exist, and so must exist. Descartes maintained that existence belongs analytically to God; it is part of his definition, just as three sides are part of the definition of a triangle.

However, I do not ...

This is a preview of the whole essay