How Plausible is Cultural Relativism

Authors Avatar

Andrew Stephen        How Plausible is Cultural Relativism?        05/07/2007

How Plausible is Cultural Relativism?

Cultural relativism associates any ethical truth to the moral precedence of a particular culture: there can be no right or wrong actions or behaviour; rather actions that either do or do not correlate with the moral code relative to a specified society. For instance, polygamy is morally acceptable in some Islamic societies but not in Christian culture. According to William Sumner, morality is simply ‘socially approved habits’ that are subjective in their nature but form moral guidelines for the relevant culture. Therefore, cultural relativism denies the existence of objective and universal moral truths in favour of an acceptance that nothing can be intrinsically wrong or right, and that any feelings of moral obligation are caused by our upbringing and cultural influences. As a result though, there are many criticisms of this meta-ethical attitude because it does appear that human morality is considerably more complex than simply a product of social precedents.

A main supporter of cultural relativism is James Rachels in ‘The Elements of Moral Philosophy.’ He agreed with the idea that all different societies have different moral codes and each of these individual codes determines what is morally acceptable within that particular society: the Cultural Difference Argument. Because there is no objective standard by which to judge which code is superior, all codes are of equal validity: it is not for a cultural relativist to judge which moral code is superior but instead to accept that both are equally applicable to their particular culture. Furthermore, it would be arrogant for somebody from one culture to judge or condemn another belief system: “cultural relativism celebrates the variety of beliefs and values held by different people.” Ostensibly, this attitude appears to be plausible: there are many examples of cultures differing in moral views in the world. For example, slavery was morally acceptable to most ancient Greeks but is not to most Europeans today. In other words, what was considered right for ancient Greeks would be wrong for today’s Europeans and this is applicable to numerous other examples. Essentially, slavery cannot be considered objectively right or wrong: any moral viewpoint is merely an opinion which differs from culture to culture. Therefore, it does seem that morality is almost arbitrary from a cultural relativist perspective, because it simply becomes a “description of the values held by a particular society at a particular time” as opposed to a standard of right and wrong. The Cultural Difference Argument is also flawed in a more literal sense. For instance, we believe that the earth is round whereas some tribes believe it to be flat, therefore the shape of the earth becomes a matter of opinion depending on one’s cultural background. Whilst this flaw seems to disprove the argument because we have reliable scientific evidence to prove the shape of the earth, it is perhaps a non-contextual counter-argument because the Cultural Difference Argument refers to non-cognitive statements of morality as opposed to a synthetic statement about the world. Nevertheless, it still raises doubts over the credibility of Rachels’ argument.

Join now!

        It is also possible to question Rachels’ assertation that different societies have different moral codes. All societies, for instance, prohibit murder, rape and steeling which are all actions that most humans consider morally wrong regardless of the society that they are from. On a more fundamental level, there appears to exist a basic moral drive that is similar within all humans regardless of their cultural background: “underlying our moral impulses, then, are natural sentiments of benevolence.” The desire to act positively that is evident in all cultural codes exists due to an underlying element of moral awareness that is part of ...

This is a preview of the whole essay