A Real Ideal Sense of Mind, Matter, and Self.

Authors Avatar

A Real Ideal Sense of Mind, Matter, and Self

Abstract

The Realist / Idealist dichotomy attracted the writer to the following; we immediately find ourselves in the hard-nosed, clamorous, and antiquated trenches of this polemic.  Significant proponents of the relevant camps provide the contextual background for our endeavor.  The treatment as such brings fecund opportunity to develop phenomenalist perspective of the ‘problems of philosophy’ well enough to deconstruct their premises as being nonsensical.  Phenomenal mind, matter, and self result and are oriented with the world in which we sense, know, and live:  our Universe, one with no Other.


The renowned Realist/Idealist dichotomy incited the following exploration, which began with Russell, “IS there any knowledge in the world which is so certain that no reasonable man could doubt it?”  Of what do we have indubitable knowledge?  This query, without even considering the products of its perusal, is worth exploring.  Descartes spawned the ascent of the ego by the method of systematic doubt, and developed the mind and matter polarity that knowledge must be of something; this is an ‘object’, by definition.  Are there any objects, anything, which are given, truly known to us?  A very relevant piece by Ayer, who writes as boldly as soberly:

“There are no objects whose existence is indubitable… no synthetic propositions are logically sacrosanct… All of them, including the propositions which describe the content of our sensations, are hypotheses which, however great their probability, we may eventually find it expedient to abandon.  All ‘objects’ are ‘given’ to us by sense-content.”         (121)

Consciousness may be regarded as sense-experience from sense-content, sense-data, sensation.  It may be asked, “What is a sensation and is it separate from my self?  Are sensations of something other than mind?”  Substantial queries also include, “What exactly is mind, self, and matter?”  Knowing philosophers perpetually question, by definition, I discovered this to be the tour de force of this endeavor:

Philonous:

“Can any doctrine be true that necessarily leads a man into an absurdity?

Hylas:

        “Without doubt it cannot.”                (Berkeley, 14)

This will serve as the lodestar for what lies ahead; Ayer’s strong Positivist background will valuably help us parse through many propositions.  The desired goal is remembered, though; the aforementioned dichotomy shall be described, and Ayer will reconcile the ‘existence’ of the issue and lead us away from doubt, helping us logically construct an integrated universe with which we participate from the question, “What are we?”

Berkeley’s Idealism and Russell’s Realism

The Arithmetical Paradox defines the Realist/Idealist issue well, and relates to the ‘problem of perception’. It may be represented as, “there appears to be a great multitude of these conscious egos, the world however is only one” (Schroedinger, 52).  

“One great reason why it is felt that we must secure a physical object in addition to the sense-data, is that we want the same object for different people. When ten people are sitting round a dinner-table, it seems preposterous to maintain that they are not seeing the same tablecloth, the same knives and forks and spoons and glasses. But the sense-data are private to each separate person; what is immediately present to the sight of one is not immediately present to the sight of another: they all see things from slightly different points of view, and therefore see them slightly differently.”                                                (Russell, Problems of Philosophy)

What is the common, public, “neutral” object that everyone senses?  Realists believe in the existence of a physical object which, more or less, causes the sense-data, which may happen to be perceived.  Russell describes

…a ‘real’ table, which is distinguished from the ‘sense-data’, the means by which we know of the table.  The 'real' shape is not what we see; it is something inferred from what we see. Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately experience.  It is rational to believe that our sense-data…are really signs of something existing independent of us and our perceptions.          (Problems)

Berkeley’s Hylas initially propounds Realism, “The sensation I take to be an act of the mind perceiving; beside which, there is something perceived; and I call this the object” (Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous).  Idealists hold that only the sense-data or content is known; there is no ground for believing in the presence of something synthesized from sensations, or sense-contents.

A short summary of the Realist assertions Philonous incites Hylas to reject in Berkeley’s  Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous benefits our endeavor.  Sensible qualities arise in conversation with Hylas’s describing ‘apparent’ and ‘real’ things, i.e. sense-contents in the mind and material things, respectively.  Hylas ‘owns’ that both the secondary and the primary qualities, colors and tastes and motion and extension, respectively, do not exist outside the mind, impactful for Idealist Arithmetical Paradox thought.  Leading to Hylas’s concession that sounds too have no real being outside the mind, Philonous notes the obvious paradox “that real sounds are never heard” (19).  Similar threads will continue to strain these Realist conceptions.  Eventually, Hylas admits as the basis for rejecting color’s existing without mind, that no idea, nor any sensation (like color or heat), can exist in an unperceiving substance.    Before Berkeley reaches to give his own account of the neutral ‘objects’ that do exist even after leaving a room, he valiantly criticizes proposals to distinguish sensations from their objects, and the concept of material substratum.  Berkeley’s mistake was asserting, metaphysically, that the things one may sense in a room, when left alone, still existed, but only as thoughts in the mind of God.  Berkelyian Idealist presentations of pertinent arguments are valuable, though, especially contra Russell’s Realist claims.

Join now!

A pivotal aspect of Realism is its notion of matter:

“We commonly mean by 'matter' something which is opposed to 'mind', something which we think of as occupying space and as radically incapable of any sort of thought or consciousness. It is chiefly in this sense that Berkeley denies matter; that is to say, he does not deny that the sense-data which we commonly take as signs of the existence of the table are really signs of the existence of something independent of us, but he does deny that this something is nonmental…”                 (Russell, Problems)

Berkeley decides that our ...

This is a preview of the whole essay