Discuss the origin and development of Greek cosmology and cosmogony from the 8th Century to the 5th Century BC.

Authors Avatar

ΓΝΩΘΙ ΣΑΥΤΟΝ

Cosmology and Cosmogony of the Ancient Greek World

Richard Armes

Discuss the origin and development of Greek cosmology and cosmogony from the 8th Century to the 5th Century BC.

Prof. Stephen Hawking, Interview with The Guardian (UK) September 27, 2005

     Cosmology is the metaphysical study of the structure and nature of the universe as a whole. Cosmogony is the branch of ancient philosophy concerned with the origins of the universe. Since the beginning of recorded history (and no doubt before) humans have been fascinated by the questions posed by cosmological enquiry and investigations concerning the birth of our universe. Often wrong, but never uncertain, humans have believed many incompatible answers, but there have been certain common patterns and rationales in these conclusions. The differences in these conclusions possibly reflect differences in the economy, social order, and the environment of the different civilisations. This paper shall be primarily concerned with the developments in presocratic thought, specifically that of the Ionian rationalists, for prior to the development of Greek civilisation, although men no doubt speculated on the world beyond their immediate experience, no records of their enquiries survive.

     We shall start by briefly looking at the forerunners of philosophical cosmology, with much of our emphasis being placed upon the writings of the great poets Homer and Hesiod. In the Illiad and the Odyssey, although not directly addressing ideas on cosmogony, Homer considers the Gods as being involved with daily life.

     In Theogony, the 1022 line Epic by one of the giants of Greek poetry, the writer deals with the birth (Cf. Hes. Theog. 116), resulting in the formation of several bodies, and by keeping them united it the history of the Greek gods as well as the creation of the Universe. The role of the Gods in both Homer and Hesiod indicates a long lasting tradition in cosmological understanding. Although irrational when compared to the later work of the presocratics (See Thales for earliest example: Cf. Simpl. In Phy. 23, 29 and Arist. De caelo Ba3, 294a28), a clear attempt is being made to make sense of the universe and it’s origins, a step which would inevitably lead to the development of philosophy in 8th century Greece.

     Before moving onto to an examination of presocratic ideas we shall briefly look at an intriguing example of 7th century theogonical cosmology evident from the works of the Spartan lyricist Alcman. In  Oxyrhynchus Papyrus no.2390 we are introduced to one of his poems which presents some ideas on theogonical cosmology. However, of the poem itself little survives; the papyrus preserves part of a commentary on the poem written around the 2nd century AD, which proves the poem was evidently quite puzzling and demanded various attempts at interpretation (Cf. Alch. fr. 3, col. i, 27f). Despite this, a certain resemblance to Hesiodic ideas of divine intervention with the creation of the universe and everyday life can be seen. This indicates not only a development in thought but also the continuation of popular ideas from previous centuries, indicating their importance in the development philosophical understanding in the Greek world.

     So far we have examined ideas where a background of myths and gods are seen as a primary part of explaining the development of the world. Progress was made toward philosophy by transcending the type of world-view favoured by the likes of Homer and Hesiod while reaching after a more direct view, far less symbolic and with less emphasis upon the actions of anthropomorphic deities. It was this kind of change that would take place in Greece between the 8th and 6th centuries BC. The growth of the polis together with the development of foreign contacts and a monetary system transformed the Hesiodic view of society and rendered the old heroic archetypes obsolete. However much of the rational undertone of the Homeric and Hesiodic tradition survived, but in societies like Ionia, not least in Miletus itself, they took on a more concise form and were applied to a broader and more objective model of the world.

     It was in Ionia that the first really rational attempts to explain the nature of the universe took place. During the 6th century, in the Greek colony at Miletus, a group of thinkers began to engage in an extended exploration of the speculative issues. Although these  kept few records, other ancient authorities took note of some of their central tenets. Their central urge was to show that the complex world has a simple, permanent underpinning in the  of a single kind of substance from which all else emerges.

     The philosopher Thales, for example, is remembered as having concluded that the prime substance of all things is water. Although we have no record of the reasoning that led Thales to this conclusion, but one can imagine what it might have been. If we suppose that the ultimate substance of the world must be chosen from among things familiar to us, water seems a logical choice: most of the earth is covered with it, it appears in solid, liquid, and gaseous forms, and was clear to Thales as essential to the existence of life (Cf. Hipp. i. Dox. 555). In Thales’s conclusion we see another continuing rationale in cosmological thought: the concept of a flat earth resting upon a vast expanse of water. We notice however a total abandonment of theological explanations, favouring a more rational and observational method (Cf. Arist. Met. i. 3 ; 983 b 6), a method which would have a lasting effect on the cosmological thought of the ancient Greeks.

     Thales's student , however, found the Thalean conclusion overly simplistic. In paying proper attention to the changing face of the universe, he supposed, requires us to consider the cyclical interaction of things of at least four sorts: the hot, the cold, the dry, and the wet (Cf. Arist. Phys. i. 4; 187 a 12). Anaximander held that all of these elements originally arise from a primal, turbulent mass,  or ‘Infinite’. It is only by a gradual process of distillation that everything else emerges—earth, air, fire, and water—and even living things evolve (Cf. Simpl. Phys. 32 r; 150, 20). In this conclusion we see not only an important criticism of Thalean ideas, but also a clear development in cosmological theory. While continuing the observational methods employed by Thales, we see an attempt at contemplating the notion of the ‘infinite’, a concept which would have a lasting effect on philosophical understanding throughout the following centuries (Cf. Arist. Metaph. xii. 2 ; 1069 b 18).

Join now!

     With the philosophy of Anaximander proposing that our universe is comprised of a number of different elements, his student returned to the conviction that there must be a single kind of substance at the heart of everything, and he proposed vapour or mist as the most likely candidate (Cf. Arist. Metaph. i. 3 ; 984 a 5). Not only does this warm, wet air combine two of the four elements together, but it also provides a familiar pair of processes for changes in it’s state: condensation and evaporation. Thus, in its most basic form of breath or spirit, ...

This is a preview of the whole essay