Is there such thing as a Peasant Community

Authors Avatar

Reality is just a word that begins with r and ends in y’ (Carol Shields) should Historians expunge the word ‘reality’ from their vocabulary?

The concept of ‘reality’ in historical studies is a contested one: ‘history’s anxiety now hovers over the status and meaning of the word ‘reality’’. Much historiography is grounded in ‘realist’ or ‘foudationalist’ methodology; that is scholarship that explicity attempts to reconstruct a past ‘reality’.  Indeed, history was given ‘scientific’ status by a number of scholars.   Bury’s inaugural lecture as Regius Professor at Cambridge reflects this now outdated positivism: history is a ‘science’ that has particular ‘claims’ and ‘laws’.  Historical reality, in this view, is attainable; it can be described and analyzed.  However, the notion of ‘reality’ has been convincingly challenged by scholars influenced by the linguistic turn.  Scholars such as Jenkins and Harlan have adopted the tenants of post-structuralism and have undermined the epistemological and ontological assumptions guarding the concept of ‘reality’.  History becomes a ‘shifting, problematic discourse’ unable to make claims of veracity.  Scholars such as Jenkins dissolve the distinction between ‘historical narrative’ and ‘fictional narrative’ undermining the distinction between ‘honest’ scholarship and propaganda. In Chariter’s words, ‘all capacity to choose between the true and false, to tell what happened, and to denounce falsificiations and forgers’ is lost.  It seems short-sighted and a linguistically reductive to wholly reject the notion of ‘reality’.  Lorenz, for example, drawing on Putnam, advocates ‘internal realism’; ‘reality’ exists within conceptual frameworks.  Alternatively, scholars such as Car argue that ‘action’ is structured according to ‘narrative’.   Historical analysis simply mirrors this narratively constructed ‘reality’.  It will be argued that attempts such as Lorenz and Car, while not unproblematic, should be taken seriously, but that Hayden White paradoxically provides a barrier against the excesses of linguistic relvatism.  .

Historians have always generally viewed ‘reality’ as problematic.  Ranke, himself, acknowledged that history, in contrast to other sciences, could not be “satisfied simply with recording what has been found; history requires the ability to recreate”. Indeed, Bloch in arguing that ‘questions’ have to be asked of evidence retains a large role for the creative influence of the historian. In this respect, a ‘critical method’ to source analysis allows historical scholarship to exist in a dialectical relationship with ‘reality’.  In the second half of the twentieth century the critique of ‘reconstructionist’ history grew louder with the publication of T. Kunh’s, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions in which he argued that ‘scientific’ research was undertaken within theoretical paradigms; rather than being a simple reconstruction of ‘reality’.  In the field of history, E.H. Carr noted how selection of source material was based on cultural assumptions. Historical research was viewed as struggling towards a ‘reality’ impaired by the primary material and cultural biases of the scholars; but Carr simultaneously asserted that history is not ‘something spun out of the human brain’.  The term ‘reality’ was still centre-stage in the historians vocabulary, it was however recognised as problematic and impossible to fully reconstruct.  

The ontological and epistemological assumptions behind the concept of ‘reality’ have been radically overhauled by the linguistic turn.  Barthes, drawing on Sausurian ‘structuralism’, suggested that there was no difference between history and fiction.  Reality is dissolved into a literary trope.  Indeed, White argues that historical narratives are ‘verbal fictions, the contents of which are as much invented as found and the forms of which have more in common with their counterparts in literature than they have with those in the sciences’.   Historical ‘narrative’ is ‘emploted’ and imposed, by the historian, on ‘reality’ to create meaning.  Events do not ‘speak for themselves’ but are suppressed or highlighted ‘by characterization, motific repetition, variation of tone and point of view…in short, all of the techniques that we would normally expect to find in the emplotment of a play’. The concept of ‘reality’ was rejected, in favour, of a multiplicity of literary ‘narratives’.  In this respect, the ‘word’ reality was, if not expunged, sidelined in the vocabulary of the historian, in favour for ‘narrative’ and ‘emplotment’.  

Join now!

However, scholars such as D. Carr have challenged White’s contention that historians impose ‘structure’ and ‘meaning’, on reality, through narrative.  Carr draws on a number of phenomenological perspectives to argue that narrative is a constitute aspect of human life.  Human reality is structured upon narrative: an isomorphic relationship exists between ‘reality’ and ‘narrative’.   Human agents understand experience through a ‘protentional-retentional’ process, where ‘past’, ‘present’ and ‘future’ are sequenced.  Narrative is not imposed on historical reality but drawn from it: narrative inheres ‘in the events themselves’ and ‘is an extension of one of their primary features’. In this respect, the ...

This is a preview of the whole essay