Were the Stoics Effective Critics of Slavery?

Authors Avatar

  Were the Stoics Effective Critics of Slavery?

The word ‘effective’ in the title of this paper has two meanings, which have the potential to cause ambiguity. This being, that the definition of ‘effective’ can have a meaning of, ‘having a desired effect’ and also, ‘having definite effect’. Thus, the question can be restated for clarity as being ‘Did the Stoics Have a Desired or Definite Effect as Critics of Slavery?’ The issue that these definitions raise is one of perception. The ‘having a desired effect’ definition is found through attempting to look at what the Stoics themselves desired as ‘critics of slavery’, whereas the ‘having a definite effect’ definition is more subjective and involves considering the Stoic effects upon slavery through valued judgements. On the former definition of ‘effective’ this paper will show the Stoics to have achieved what was desired, which as a consequence will be shown to be the reason why they failed to achieve the second definition of effective. In other words, it was because the Stoics in their criticisms achieved what they desired, that they failed to have any definite effects on slavery. This leads to the questioning of the Stoics position as ‘critics of slavery’.

Stoicism is named after the Stoa Poecile (painted porch), where it was first taught. Founded by Zeno of Citiam it was divided into three parts, namely logic, physics and ethics. After Zeno, Cleanthenes became head of the school and it seemed as though the philosophy would split into many factions due mainly to its holistic nature. Chrysippus of Solia, a pupil of Cleanthenes is generally regarded to have saved Stoicism by creating a formulation which was accepted as the general standard. That is not to say that Stoics did not disagree, but there were generally agreed principles.

In relation to the question of this paper the Stoics held complicated beliefs that at first seem contradictory. They believed in exceptionless laws of fate in which everything happened according to providence, at the same time as being ‘combatibilists’, in which human action is morally responsible. Also, the Stoics held the view that virtue was sufficient for happiness and that nothing except virtue was good. These beliefs in themselves are not enough in themselves to be compatible with a slave society, but it will be shown that those concerning fate and virtue were the tools the Stoics used to not be at odds with slavery.

Little is known about the effect of Stoicism on the early Hellenistic world that it was created in. It was not until Diogenes of Babylon (240-152 BC), Panaetius from Rhodes (185-109 BC) and Posidonius (135-51 BC) that evidence becomes significant. This period is called the ‘Middle Stoa’ and is significant for being a time when Stoicism changed to make itself more accessible to educated Romans. The ‘Late Stoa’ was marked by a period where the there was a move away from philosophical argument, and a move towards presenting Stoicism as a moral way of life. This can be seen in the letters and essays of Lucius Annaeus Seneca, the essays of Musonius Rufus, the reported lectures of Epictetus and the meditations of Marcus Aurelius. Despite changes in Stoicism to suit the Roman world, from philosophical to moralising concerns, Stoicism maintained its essential principles.

The Roman Empire like the Athenian polis is termed a slave society, being a society in which slaves were part of its intrinsic makeup. Bradley makes the point that ‘Slavery was not ignored’. From a modern perspective it is surprising how often slaves are discussed by the Stoics. We have work that discusses slaves from most of the major figures in Stoicism during the Roman period. This is primarily due to two factors. Firstly we can see in the work of the Stoic writer Aulus Geliius that it was not uncommon for slaves to become philosophers. He points out that Phaedon of Elis, Menippus. Pompylus, Peraeus, Mys, Diogenes the Cynic and Epictetus were all slaves. This link, less common in other facets or the Roman world must have made slavery a topic often discussed, and therefore a topic for philosophical discourse. Secondly, and more importantly, discussion on slaves was a useful philosophical tool to illustrate that a free man according to classical standards could be a slave unless he seeks virtue. Apart from the slaves who managed to become philosophers, Stoicism like all philosophy was the pursuit of the upper classes. This was primarily due to time money and tradition in the classical world.

Join now!

 Before the beliefs on slavery that the Stoics held are to be considered the position in society that the major Stoics held needs to be established, because Stoics could not have been effective critics of slavery if they did not hold positions of power to influence and implement opinions and laws.

Panaetius of Rhodes (185-109 BC) was of noble birth, he moved to Rome in 140’s and like Polybius he was part of the entourage of Paullus Carnelius Scipio Aemilianus, who reached the position of consul and censor. In this role Panaetius would have been in a position ...

This is a preview of the whole essay