What is required for autonomy, and do we fulfil those requirements?

Authors Avatar

        What is required for autonomy, and do we fulfil those requirements?

MEST 0205

What is required for autonomy, and do we fulfil those requirements?

10th January 2005

When attempting to describe the conditions required for autonomy, one must first understand the definition of autonomy in the context of rationality.  The Oxford English Dictionary definition which most conforms to this idea of autonomy reads ‘Freedom (of the will); the Kantian doctrine of the will, apart from any object willed; opp. to heteronomy 1817.’  The reference to Kant in this definition stems from his classification of the terms autonomy and heteronomy in his treatise Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals which explores the idea of free will and autonomy.  Kant’s idea of autonomy is that universal law is given through the wills of all rational beings, where the wills of persons are not subject to the rule of another being or power.

In the humanist view of the world, there is an assumption that persons can be distinguished from other creatures due to their responsibility and free will – the autonomy of their actions; it is because we perceive people to be responsible that we judge them for their actions, be it through praise or gratitude, criticism or contempt, and we also feel pride or shame in our own actions or achievements as we believe we are responsible for them; we take ‘responsible beings more seriously than those we identify as ‘nonresponible’.  This view can however be challenged, once we try to establish what exactly it is that leads us to hold someone responsible for their actions, when taking into account the many circumstances that already exist where we do not attribute responsibility.  Wolf gives the examples of dogs and cats, young children, the insane and severely mentally retarded adults as those which we do not regard as responsible beings though they may have potentially effective wills; the dog learns to be house trained through the coercion of its owner, but one would not describe it as responsible for fouling the pavement, indeed, it is the responsible owner who would be fined for such an occurrence.  If we are to be confident in our distinction between persons and things, however, we must lay down the conditions required for one to be a person.

To look at various unsatisfactory definitions of this distinction, we first arrive at the simple notion that ‘I am a person’, therefore a person can be defined as what I am.  However, this ‘I’ lacks content, it allows us to know that we exist as in the case of Descartes’ cogito ergo sum, where this ambiguity is the essence of the phrase.  To describe a person as merely a human being is also a fallacy, as although it would closely match the definition, according to Harry Frankfurt ‘it is conceptually possible that members of novel or even of familiar non-human species should be persons and…that some members of the human species are not persons’; we know of people that are considered to be mentally incapable, and thus have diminished responsibility in a court of law, for example, and though they are yet undiscovered, extra terrestrial life forms may exist which would meet our criteria for being a person.

Descartes has the idea that a person exists immaterially, a mind and soul, and does not depend on any material thing.  However, if we are not to view ourselves as a mind divorced completely from a body, this becomes less coherent; can we conceive a person to be just a soul and ignore everything physical?  Yet Descartes’ criteria to distinguish persons from machines can give us a better idea of personhood.  The first criterion, the idea of linguistic competence is one also used by Chomsky in order to challenge the linguistic capabilities of birds and primates, who may seem to be able to communicate with us, stating that machines could never match our linguistic creativity.  Even the least academically able person is able to construct unique phrases through a basic vocabulary and an understanding of grammar, though admittedly there may now be computers capable of creating unique text once they have ‘learned’ the structures of language.  The second says that ‘although [machines] do many things as well as or even better than any of us…they would not act through understanding, but only according to the disposition of their organs.’* This action through understanding gives us the idea that the actions of a person, unlike those of an animal or machine, can be explained through reasons, or the desires of the person carrying out the action.  Nonetheless, there being innumerable circumstances where animals act according to reasons, this definition still falls short.  It is the freedom to make those decisions which defines a person, the idea of free will and autonomy.  As will be explored later on in this essay, if we cannot classify ourselves as autonomous beings, then maybe we cannot distinguish ourselves from the animals we see as inferior, as though the power of speech makes us superior in some respect, without the idea of autonomy, we lose responsibility for our actions, and are controlled by the same forces of nature that mean the rabbit will always run away from the fox.

Join now!

This idea is explored in great depth in Frankfurt’s article ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’, in which the idea of acting upon desires is crucial to the definition of persons, his view being that ‘one essential difference between persons and other creatures is to be found in the structure of a person’s will.’  According to Frankfurt, a distinction is possible in persons between one’s desires which actually transpire into actions, and those which one wants to constitute one’s will, proposing that the statement ‘Α wants to X’ could be consistent with even the seemingly mutually ...

This is a preview of the whole essay