One is only justified in punishing individual offenders on the basis that they deserve punishment, it hence follows only those receiving punishment should deserve it - discussed

Authors Avatar

I would generally agree that one is only justified in punishing individual offenders on the basis that they deserve punishment, it hence follows only those receiving punishment should deserve it. Sentencing practice is that punishment is based not only on the crime and the circumstances of the crime, but also on the aims of the sentencing. A detailed explanation of the effects of aggravating and mitigating circumstances is not appropriate here, a mere appreciation of the consequent individualism that goes into the majority of sentences is sufficient. Exceptions to the norm shall be discussed later.

Punishment must meet the needs of both individual and society and there are four competing theories as to why we should punish. The retributive theory looks back to the crime, and punishes because of what has been done. The other three theories, namely deterrence, incapacitation and rehabilitation, look ahead to the consequences of punishment and as a result try to achieve crime reduction. They are often called consequentialist or utilitarian theories.

Deterrence theories are concerned with the consequences of punishment on others’ future actions. Their aim is to reduce further crime by example or by threat of punishment. In theory, deterrence operates at three levels. Individual or specific deterrence hopes that the suffering endured from previous punishment will be so influential that the criminal will not reoffend. Here the sentencer faces a difficult challenge in that he/she has to select the sentence (anything from absolute discharge to imprisonment) which is going to have the most appropriate impact on the offender so as to deter them in future. General deterrence focuses on deterring everyone from committing the crime. At the legislative level, Parliament lays down penalties to threaten those who might contemplate crime. At the sentencing level, punishment of offenders is hoped to discourage others from committing similar crime. According to this model, over-punishment or exemplary sentencing of one offender may be justified. At the social level, unemployment and other consequences arising as a result of convictions may act as a deterrent to others. Finally, educative deterrence aims at introducing law-abiding habits. For example, take the use of the office telephone for private phone calls. This is a criminal offence which carries a maximum penalty of five years’ imprisonment. However, the lack of convictions leads people to believe this conduct is not so wrongful as physical theft from the office. If a number of people were to become convicted of such an offence, the likely result is that the majority of people would see this offence in the same light as physical theft.

Deterrence theories are fraught with problems and the effectiveness of deterrence is hard to measure.

Every time a ‘traditional’ (i.e. a crime already covered by precedent – hence theoretically having a deterrence effect) crime is committed, does this not weaken the argument for deterrence sentencing? According to N Walker:

“Naive beliefs both in the effectiveness and the ineffectiveness of a policy of deterrence have been replaced by the less exciting realisation that some people can be deterred in some situations from some types of conduct by some degree of likelihood that they will be penalised in some ways; but that we do not yet know enough to enable us to be very specific about the people, the situations, the conduct, or the likelihood or nature of the penalties.”

Drawing on the work of Andenaes, the effectiveness of sentencing theory can be improved by increasing the severity of the sentencing; “Contemporary dictatorships display with almost frightening clarity the conformity that can be produced by a ruthlessly severe justice system”. However, the deterrence theory assumes a rational thinking behind all our actions, looking at the potential losses and gains. This view is clearly incorrect - or we would be left with a virtually crime free society, where only ‘new’ (i.e. those not covered by precedent) crimes would be committed.

However, across the spectrum of society the capacity of people to see ‘danger’ varies from the completely ‘blind’, i.e. those “prisoners who are quite incapable of foresight, who cannot learn even from the experience of punishment, much less from the threat of it.”, to those who are so deterred as to commit no crime in their lives. For people incapable of foresight, it has been suggested that perhaps the only way of deterring them from further criminal offences, is to punish someone to whom is ‘special’ to them, for instance their wife or child. This would clearly be an exception to the opening statement as the family would not deserve punishment, but other than life long imprisonment, as it stands the criminal justice system is quite incapable of controlling some criminals.

Join now!

Incapacitation simply removes a person’s ability to commit further crime, whether it be through removal of driving licence, imposing a curfew or imprisonment. In the case of Sargent Lawton LJ described persons suitable for such punishment as “offenders for whom neither deterrence nor rehabilitation works. They will go on committing crimes as long as they are able to do so. In those cases the only protection which the public has is that such persons should be locked up for a long period.” Lawton LJ mentions only persistent criminals here, but one must also consider those who commit ‘one-off’ crimes so ...

This is a preview of the whole essay