What criticisms might be made of the Roman law of theft?

Authors Avatar

-Roman Law Week 4- What criticisms might be made of the Roman law of theft.

Theft (furtum) is one of four delicts considered by Justinian, along with robbery (rapina), damage (damnum iniuria datum) and outrage (iniuria); according to Thomas, a delict consisted in wrongful conduct causing harm, for which the aggrieved party recovered damages. In terms of theft, Gaius fails to provide us with a definition but Justinian describes furtum as “a fraudulent handling [contrectatio] of a thing, of its use or the possession of it, and this is forbidden by natural law.” It must be noted that Justinian fails to refer to the fact that furtum only applies to res mobiles that are in commercio. In this essay, I will criticize the Roman law of theft in terms of the difference between the legal definition of furtum and the popular conception, in terms of furtum manifestum and non manifestum and in terms of the practical application of the penal remedies against an insolvent thief. I will also criticise the condictio furtiva, the lack of actio furti in cases of furtum between slaves and families, and the fact that rapina is viewed by the Institutes as lying outside of the law of furtum.

Firstly, a criticism of the law of theft is described by Ibetson, in the fact that the legal definition of furtum as contrectatio and the popular conception that theft required the carrying off of the res. Contrectatio is described as a physical handling but also as any meddling or dealing with the thing by Nicholas, with Buckland and Thomas agreeing that contrectatio meant handling of the stolen thing. However, this contrectatio had to be fraudulosa ie. affected with the intention of wrongdoing with the lack of consent on the part of the victim, to the appropriation of the thing. Indeed, Ibetson says that this mental state could be animus furandi which was “an intention to steal which clearly involved more than an intention to handle.” According to Ibetson, the definition of furtum as contrectatio did not displace the basic conception of furtum as involving the actual removal of property as in origin furtum required the actual carrying off, asportation, of the stolen thing; this is demonstrated by the fact that subripere  was the word most commonly used to describe the act of stealing, Paul’s reference to the derivation from ferre to auferre and Aulus Gellius’s hinting at the fact that furtum requires a carrying off.  Hence, Ibetson establishes that the definition of furtum as contrectatio was therefore established as something different from its underlying conception of carrying away. This is best demonstrated in the case of a heavy chest where one has the intention to take the whole chest and all the contents after having been through them but the case is too heavy to take as a whole. If one is caught carrying off just one item from that chest, he is in fur manifestus only for the item that he actually takes; animus fruandi for the whole but furtum for only what is taken.

Join now!

Other criticisms of the Roman law of theft pertain to the distinction between furtum manifestum and furtum non manifestum. Firstly, the lack of consensus between the jurists as to the meaning furtum manifestum is worthy of criticism. Gaius describes furtum manifestum as “when the thief is taken in the act, but others extend it to cover the case of the thief being taken in the place where the act was committed” and it would appear he concurs with this as he disagrees with the assertion that “it is manifest theft until the thief has carried the stolen property to the place to which ...

This is a preview of the whole essay