Modern life-prolonging technologies have sharpened some ancient dilemmas on the value of life.

Authors Avatar

Modern life-prolonging technologies have sharpened some ancient dilemmas on the value of life. Our ability to sustain vital signs virtually as long as we wish pointedly raises the question whether we value life for its electrical efflorescence or for qualities that might be enjoyed by the person whose life is in jeopardy. In fact, it raises the question what the life is that we value. Is it biology or biography?

Our legal norms and moral intuitions evolved before we had techniques to separate vital signs from interesting personality, before we could hold the dying in a living death and perpetuate a hopeless limbo of darkness and electricity. They developed during the long pre-technological age in medicine when the cessation of breath and pulse always coincided with the cessation of brain function and consciousness. But these no longer coincide.

Nearly every hospital in the country has the equipment, and occasionally the incentive, to preserve heartbeat and respiration in bodies not brain dead but subject to a permanent and total loss of higher brain function. Because many states have not accepted brain death as their legal definition of death, it also happens that hospitals occasionally have the incentive to prolong vital signs in bodies past the point of brain death. This was physically impossible until the past three decades. Our medical cleverness has increased much faster than our willingness to think about the ethics and metaphysics of death. This moral and legal vacuum has left physicians, patients, families, and courts without guidance as to when biological animation is life inviolate, to be protected at all costs, and when it is just electrical twitching —or something in between.

The very lack of moral and legal guidance has been an incentive to increase our ability to preserve vital signs ad nauseam. Fearing liability, physicians employ more and more heroic methods to preserve life in the form of vital signs even when life in the form of hopeful consciousness has been irretrievably lost. The more heroic methods they use, the more the duty to preserve merely cardio-pulmonary life is rendered a grotesque anachronism. This vicious circle is not inescapable. But it can only be broken by clarity and courage: the clarity to look closely at complex questions and the courage to make very difficult decisions without much help from our unequipped ethical, religious, and legal traditions.[Note 1] We must rethink the nature and value of life.

Toward the end of Section 2 I will briefly examine the consequences of failing in this courage. If it is true that our technical innovations in medicine have made certain difficult choices necessary, and if we shirk the responsibility of making those choices, pretending that nothing of moral significance has changed, then at least we should know what evils might now emerge that would not have emerged in the pre-technological age of medicine.

As we approach the threshold —the precipice— of the perfect ability to enliven any cadaver with sparks we must fill the moral and legal vacuum with the results of our clear and courageous reflection, or we will have made our technology a fetish without making life more secure. The moral position which upholds the "sanctity of life" does not fill so much as codify this moral vacuum. It does not rethink the nature and value of life, but clings for security to the indiscriminate consecration of animate signs.

The phrase "sanctity of life" occurs frequently in modern discussion, yet is rarely explicated and understood. Nor are its grounds or alternatives often examined. Too often the position is painted as the only one in the field for people who abhor murder. But the position is not that comprehensive or exclusive in fact, and when articulated must give up some of the territory it occupies by virtue of vagueness and moral bullying.

To say that life has sanctity (or is sacred) is normally to say that life per se has sanctity. For the assertion is meant to be distinguished from the view that the value of a life may depend on its quality, condition, or circumstances. To the sanctity of life proponent, lives have sanctity regardless of the degree or kind of suffering, deterioration, dependency, or development they manifest, and regardless of the imminence of death, the burden on others, and the wishes of the subject to live or die.

Therefore, the sanctity of life position is opposed to any position that allows the value of a life to vary with its condition or circumstances. Such positions are usually collected under the name "quality of life" theories. The contrast is real, but much remains to be done to show the fuller meaning of the two positions. Each position is actually a cluster of variations, and much of the task of clarification will be to show that one need not affirm all that one's fellow travelers affirm.

For convenience I will refer to the sanctity of life position as "SL", and the quality of life position as "QL".

Before proceeding I should acknowledge that the medical cleverness which created the difficulties on which I focus here has not only relieved untold suffering, but has made many previously intractable ethical problems simply disappear. A dramatic example is the effect of antiseptic surgery, which first made possible Caesarean sections which were safe for the mother. Before the 19th century, if a fetus were hydrocephalic or for any other reason could not pass through the birth canal, physicians and families had a simple, painful choice. They could perform a Caesarean section to save the child, entailing the almost certain death of the mother. Or they could save the mother by avoiding any surgical incision, kill the fully developed fetus in utero, and remove it in pieces. If it presented head first, the skull was pierced with an iron poker, the brain scooped out, the skull crushed, and the rest of the body removed. In case of a breech birth, pieces of the fetus were removed one by one with various hooks, blades, and grippers.[Note 2] 

I believe it an unqualified good that safe Caesarean sections are now possible, permitting both the mother and hydrocephalic child to survive at very small risk. And this is only one of hundreds of examples. Hence, my complaint is not with the progress of medical science and technology in themselves. I object to the ethical fear and torpidity —what Santayana called moral cramp— that has refused to recognize that certain technical developments have changed the nature of death.

Section 1 and Section 2 describe the SL and QL positions, their variations, and points of disagreement. The argument against SL is detailed in Section 3. In Section 4 I consider the risks of putting QL into practice.

Section 1. The Sanctity of Life Position

What does it mean to attribute sanctity —as opposed to very great value— to a life? The answer seems to have these two parts:

  1. The value of life exceeds all other values. No other value overrides the value of life except possibly more life.
  2. All lives are of equal value. No single life deserves priority over another, not even the most fit, hopeful, and developed over the most vegetative, wretched, or immature. Possibly a plurality of lives may take priority over any single life, or a single life may take another in self-defense.

The first of these may be called the ultimity condition, and the second, the equality condition.[Note 3] The ultimity condition makes it easy (and necessary) to choose life over all nonlife values. The equality condition makes it impossible to choose among lives when tragic scarcity of resources makes choice necessary.

SL proponents may disagree on whether these conditions permit preventive killing, as in self-defense or to save a greater number of lives. But preventive killing will not provide a criterion to choose among lives when, for example, medical resources are too scarce to help all who need them. In cases of scarcity it may contingently —and frequently— be the case that more must be left to die than are saved, rather than vice versa. But even when the existing resources can help a majority rather than a minority, the "license" from theory to save some at the expense of others does not help select the lucky ones to survive. While solving the selection problem will be a primary reason to put aside SL for QL, SL proponents need not believe their theory is weakened by its failure to solve it. If lives are equally valuable, then it is a sign of the tragedy of life, not the weakness of the theory of equality, that some decisions are unmakeable.

I will not elaborate interesting variants of the equality condition, although several may be cited: all those lives under the jurisdiction of this legal system are of equal value and may be given priority over aliens; all "innocent" lives are of equal value and may be given priority over non-innocent lives; all human lives are of equal value and may be given priority over non-human lives; all those lives able to pay for treatment are of equal value and may be given priority over the indigent; all lives in being (to use the legal phrase) are of equal value and may be given priority over future lives; all lives closely related to the agent may be favored over other lives; all lives are of equal value except in times of war, shortage of resources, or other emergency.

While these will not be elaborated here, they will be discussed further in Section 3 as strategies by which SL may respond to objections. For now we simply pose this question: can SL use any of these two-tiered equality conditions without thereby becoming a QL position?

The ultimity condition has several variants which should be kept distinct. Here are three of the most important:

Absolute SL: Life is of absolute value. No other value is absolute. Hence, no other value ever overrides the value of life, except possibly more life.

Infinite SL: Life is of infinite value. There may be other infinite values and, as Cantor showed, not all infinities are equal. No finite values in any combination may override the value of life.

Maximum SL: Life may be of finite value, but if so, nothing has infinite value and life is the greatest finite value. Hence, no other single value ever overrides the value of life, except possibly more life. Some combinations of other values, separately insufficient, may conceivably override the value of a life.

What follows are some elaborations and comparisons of these three types of SL positions. It may be skipped by the reader who wants to get on to the contrast of SL generally with QL. (Skip to the next section.)

A general form of the equality condition is probably implied by all three types of the ultimity condition, although it implies none of them. The equality condition seems to be a necessary but not sufficient condition of any SL position. That it is insufficient is seen from the fact that it says nothing about the value of life as against other values. It is consistent with the view that the comfort of an elite, the convenience of kin, or the golf appointments of physicians are values which exceed the value of life.

Infinite and Maximum SL are variations on Absolute SL designed to make the theory compatible with different cosmologies. In mathematics we have known since the late 19th century that not all infinities are equal, and that among equal infinities some are proper subsets of others. This is not a mere technicality. Josiah Royce, for example, wanted to say that the human spirit was "infinite" but nevertheless inferior to the spirit of God. He was the first to use Cantor's transfinite cardinals to express this duality. In SL terms, life has infinite value but might still be overridden by other, greater infinite values, such as the will of the deity or certain combinations of life.[Note 4] 

This variation is important because it shows that SL may allow some nonlife values to override the value of life, but only if they are of a special type. No SL position can allow extremities of pain, cost, indignity, insentience, or hopelessness to override the value of life. While Infinite SL proponents can consistently believe that there are values worth dying for, these causes must be those of god, not country; they must be richer infinities than the human, not values derivative from the human infinite such as a vision of the good life or a good death.

Maximum SL states that life is the greatest finite value, and that that value is the highest anywhere, i.e. there are no infinite values. This variation is important because it shows that SL need not be religious. It need not posit a universe of gods, spirits, or any infinite values.

Many philosophers have pointed out that a belief in the sanctity of life does not automatically entail the absolute wrongness of all kinds of killing. If we have a duty to preserve, lengthen, and create life, we might also have competing duties which in some circumstances are overriding. This move is possible only in Infinite and Maximum SL, not in Absolute SL. It is even easier in softer positions that assert merely, e.g. that life is valuable. Because the ultimity condition makes the value of life supreme, I will assume that SL makes the the duties to life overriding in any conflict of duties. Even for Infinite and Maximum SL, which permit some combinations of other values override some number of lives, the balance tilts back in favor of life when enough lives are added to the picture.

Despite the logical possibilities opened by Infinite and Maximum SL, we find that most SL proponents seem to hold the Absolute SL position. They speak as though the value of life were infinite and that no value whatsoever could override the value of life except possibly more life.

Preventive Killing 

The question of preventive killing arises in many settings. It arose very sharply in the birth of hydrocephalic children prior to the development of antiseptic Caesarean sections. Killing the infant would prevent the mother's death; killing the mother (a foreseeable effect of a Caesarean section) could prevent the infant's death. It arises now in the killing of abortion doctors by "pro-life" activists.[Note 5] 

To those who affirm the equality condition of SL, killing one person to save another is not a bargain, even if it is permissible as in self-defense. But to kill some to save more is agonizing precisely because it is not forbidden by the principle.

Most SL proponents in practice are stymied by the question whether one life may be sacrificed to save many. Many support the death penalty, self-defense in excuse of homicide, and certain wars on the theory that more lives are saved than lost. But they resist generalizing the principle to an arithmetic formula.

Whether preventive killing is ever permissible depends on how SL proponents finish articulating their principle. It could be impermissible, permissible but not obligatory, or obligatory. If permissible or obligatory, then again depending on how the theory is completed, the selection of the life to sacrifice (to eat on the life-boat, to deny access to dialysis) could be made to depend on chance, on QL criteria, or on a combination by which QL criteria narrowed the field and chance picked the final victim.

Again, if sacrificing some life to save more is permissible or obligatory, then SL proponents may disagree on the net gain needed to justify the sacrifice. For example, to sacrifice n lives to save n + m lives may depend for its permissibility on the magnitudes of n and m. If n were 100 and m were 1, then few would assent (kill 100 to save 101), while if those numbers were reversed, then many would assent (kill 1 to save 101), even though in both cases the general principle of sacrificing fewer for more is the same. Without supplementing their original principle, SL proponents cannot distinguish killing 1 to save 101 and killing 100 to save 101, although most would distinguish these cases intuitively. Nor (if they permit preventive killing) could they distinguish killing a few poor people to save many rich people, or the sacrifice of the healthy for the terminally ill, the joyous for the suicidal, mothers for children, embryos, or zygotes, and so on, although again most would find these cases very different.

Join now!

There are strict SL proponents who do not allow some life to be sacrificed to save more life. In the life-boat cases in which the passengers draw lots to kill and eat one of their number, these proponents have asserted that each passenger had a duty to starve to death before taking another life. These proponents would not kill in self-defense. This position is not the same as the Socratic principle that it is better to suffer injustice than to do it; but it would be the same if we added the proposition that killing, even in self-defense and bona ...

This is a preview of the whole essay