A study of the philosophy of St Anselm with particular reference to the Ontological Argument.

Authors Avatar

Charlotte Drage

A study of the philosophy of St Anselm with particular reference to the Ontological Argument

History

Anselm of Canterbury, also known as Anselm of Aosta and Anselm of Bec or Saint Anselm, was first a student, then a monk, later prior and finally abbot of the monastery of Bec in Normandy, before being elected Archbishop of Canterbury in 1093. He remains one of the best-known and most readily engaging philosophers and theologians of medieval Europe.

Anselm was born of noble lineage in the Burgundian town of Aosta, near the border of the Kingdom of Lombardy (now in Italy).  In 1056, however, several years after his mother’s death and as a result of his father’s hostility, Anselm left home. Some three years later, following intermittent studies, he arrived at the Benedictine Abbey of Bec in Normandy, having journeyed there to place himself under the tutelage of the Abbey’s prior and schoolmaster, Lanfranc of Pavia. He was then twenty-six years old.

After his father’s death Anselm chose to enter the monastic order at Bec rather than return to the family estate. In 1063 he was elected prior of Bec, succeeding Lanfranc, who had been called to the abbey of St.-Etienne in Caen; in 1078 he was chosen abbot, in spite of his disinclination to assume the office. He showed even more reluctance and protestation when selected as archbishop of Canterbury in 1093, again in succession to Lanfranc.

Anselm’s subsequent quarrels with William II (son of William the Conqueror) and with his brother and successor Henry I are well known. He contested William’s exercise of jurisdiction over the church, in particular William’s claim that he alone, as king, was entitled to convoke future reform synods and had the right to decide which rival for the papacy – Urban II or Clement III – to recognize. Relations became so tense that Anselm, acting on his own initiative, chose to leave England for three years (November 1097–September 1100) to consult with Urban II in Rome. Upon his return to England after William’s death, he then quarrelled with Henry I over Urban’s injunction against any bishop doing homage to a king or being invested with his bishop’s office by a king or any other layman. Anselm, at Henry’s behest, once again departed from England for three years (April 1103–August 1106), this time to consult with Pope Paschal II. Three years later some sort of compromise was reached: the king gave way on the question of investitures and Anselm made certain concessions in the matter of bishops doing homage to the king.  He then returned to England and resumed his functions as archbishop.  But he did not live long after this, for he died on April 21, 1109.  He was canonized in 1163.  

Literary Corpus

During Anselm’s time many had come to believe that Christianity could be understood only by faith, and theology had been reduced to commentaries on the Bible.  Belief in a deity was often assumed but rarely questioned.  Anselm, however, allowed philosophy a distinct role within theology.  While he believed that the content of the Christian faith could be given only by revelation, ‘reason seeks to understand what faith believes’.  Anselm sought to provide a ‘proof’ of God which would work by reason, but which would be in accordance with the Christian faith.  

Anselm’s literary corpus consists of eleven treatises or dialogues, the most important of which are the theological work Cur deus homo (Why God Became Man) and the philosophical works Monologion (Monologue, originally entitled An Example of Meditation on the Grounds of Faith) and Proslogion (Address, originally entitled Faith Seeking Understanding).  He also left three meditations, nineteen prayers, 374 extant letters and a collection of philosophical fragments.  

Though his principal writings at Bec were more philosophical while his foremost writings as archbishop were more theological, we must still remember that Anselm himself made no express distinction between philosophy and theology, that at Bec he also wrote two meditations and sixteen prayers, and that his Cur deus homo and De concordia, in dealing with the weighty theological doctrines of atonement, predestination and grace, incorporate philosophical concepts such as necessitas praecedens (preceding necessity) and necessitas sequens (subsequent necessity).

The central thrust of the Cur deus homo may be discerned from the title: namely, to explain why it was necessary for God, in the person of the Son, to become a man.  Anselm undertakes an elaborate demonstration of his view that only by means of incarnation could God have made provision for human salvation.

Anselm’s detailed theory of satisfaction for sin was in large measure a putative theoretical justification of the institutionalized practices of the confessional and the penitential system as found in the medieval Christian church, which understood every sin to constitute a punishable demerit and to require both the imploring of God’s forgiveness and the making of amends for having dishonoured him. Throughout the intricate and sustained reasoning of the Cur deus homo, Anselm seeks to show one central truth: ‘because only God can make this satisfaction and only a man ought to make it, it is necessary that a God-man make it’ (Cur deus homo II, 6).

Join now!

As in the Cur deus homo, so also in his other treatises Anselm proceeds insofar as he deems possible, sola ratione (by recourse to rational considerations alone). Accordingly, he is acknowledged to be the ‘Father of Scholasticism’. Anselm endeavours to show that revealed truths can be established on an independent rational basis, understanding “ratio” in a broad sense, broad enough to encompass appeals to experience as well as to conceptual intelligibility.  

Philosophical Works

Anselm wrote his philosophical dialogue, De grammatico (On [an] Expert in Grammar) during his time at Bec.  The central question raised within the dialogue is utrum grammaticus ...

This is a preview of the whole essay