Sovereignty, opinion and revolution in Edmund Burke.

Authors Avatar

History of European Ideas 25 (1999) 99}120

Sovereignty, opinion and revolution

in Edmund Burke

Richard Bourke*

Department of English, Queen Mary and Westxeld College, Mile End Road, London E1 4NS, UK

1. Introduction

Edmund Burke's involvement in the politics of empire during the mid-1760s obliged

him to confront the practical signi"cance of the doctrine of sovereignty at the very

outset of his parliamentary career. This confrontation was to recur throughout his

published writings over the next 30 years. It took the form of a sustained attempt to

elucidate the relationship between liberty and authority both in Britain and between it

and the extended empire [1]. The defence of liberty as it appears in Burke's commentaries

on the American crisis, on Ireland and on the Indian sub-continent had been

a defence of moderate government. There was a connection in his mind between

moderation in government and the security of property in modern states, but ultimately

moderation implied a kind of commerce and compatibility between the

designs of rulers and the aspirations of the ruled. It had always, however, been part of

Burke's case that moderate government had to be founded on an absolute and uni"ed

sovereignty. As he put it in 1765, the &unlimited Nature of the supreme legislative

authority' was &very clear and very undeniable' [2]. Supremacy implied that ultimate

authority within a state, a confederation or an empire knew no bounds. It could not

therefore be divided, although its powers could be shared.

The &unlimited' nature of sovereignty had been formulated with particular force and

clarity by Thomas Hobbes in the 1640s. Part of his purpose had been to show that

a people had no natural right of appeal against established political authority and by

1791 Burke was not only mounting the same argument, but he was doing so in the

same language. In the Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs, Burke was to insist that

a &number of men in themselves' have no &collective capacity'. They have therefore no

collective rights which belong to them as a matter of natural entitlement and they

have in particular no natural right of rebellion. Rights pertain to &a people' as

* Corresponding author. Tel.:#171-775-3341.

0191-6599/00/$ - see front matter ( 2000 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved.

PII: S 0 1 9 1 - 6 5 9 9 ( 9 9 ) 0 0 0 2 6 - 1

1 David Hume supplies his own estimate of Temple in Ref. [8]. Burke's indebtedness to Hume is

discussed by Paul Lucas [9]. On Burke's debt to Smith, see Donald Winch [10].

established by political society, not to individuals as imagined in a state of nature. The

&idea of a people', as Burke put it, &is the idea of a corporation'. A corporation is to be

understood as a unity of individuals in a single body, as precisely a corporate entity.

Their unity, however, is the product of human contrivance. It is for that reason &wholly

arti"cial' and cannot reasonably be used as a means of securing the putatively

&natural' obligations of public authority to its incorporated members [3].

According to Burke, the failure to grasp the implications of this argument could be

observed not only among French revolutionary theorists, but also among signi"cant

sections of British Whigs in the 1790s: &These new whigs hold, that the sovereignty,

whether exercised by one or many, did not only originate from the people2but that,

in the people the same sovereignty constantly and unalienably resides' [4]. It has been

a common assumption in accounts of 18th-century political thought that the doctrine

of sovereignty somehow disappeared or became confused after the 17th century. In the

words of one commentator, it became &blunted or obscured' under the in#uence of

Montesquieu [5, but see also for example 6,7]. In this article, I want to argue that it is

20th-century scholarship rather than Montesquieu, or Rousseau, or Hume, or Burke

that has distorted the issue. In F.H. Hinsley's account, Montesquieu, together with the

American Founding Fathers, con#ated the doctrine of sovereignty with the principle

of mixed government and thereby justi"ed &the deliberate division of sovereignty itself

among several di!erent owners' [5]. In fact neither Montesquieu nor the Federalists

wrote in defence of a division of sovereignty, although they did write in defence of

a division of the powers of government. The distinction is of course crucial. I want to

argue that similarly Burke's defence of moderate government, which in Britain

implied a partition of civil powers, was part of a defence of the absolute and indivisible

character of sovereign authority. That involves showing how he was committed to

a version of limited government which was entirely compatible with a commitment to

a supreme and unitary arbiter in the a!airs of the state.

On Burke's understanding government could be limited not by the rights of

popular resistance but by the practical reality of its dependence upon the consent of

the ruled. Consent took the form of at least implied social acclamation. It was

therefore not a legal entitlement, but a practical requirement in the interest of peace

and prosperity. This amounted to saying that government depended on the opinion of

the governed. In the 17th-century, that argument had been given detailed exposition

by William Temple, but it was taken up in the 18th by David Hume and Adam Smith.

It was also adopted by Edmund Burke.1 The realisation that government rests upon

opinion supplies the key to his understanding of how moderate governments function

in the context of an absolute sovereignty, and it supplies the terms in which he sought

to disarm the impact of revolutionary doctrine through the 1790s. The alliance of

government and opinion was best enhanced through a simultaneous separation and

co-ordination of the powers of the state, not by a parcelling out of sovereignty into

various discrete compartments.

100 R. Bourke / History of European Ideas 25 (1999) 99}120

2. War and sovereignty

In February 1790, on the #oor of the House of Commons, Edmund Burke

drew attention to the situation of France as a divided sovereignty which stood on

the brink of political anarchy. The military power of the state had been encouraged

to pursue a multitude of purposes in excess of its more regular duty of defence.

But more disturbingly, a municipal army confronted the forces of the Louis XVI,

with either faction commanded in accordance with divergent principles of national

allegiance. Under these circumstances, with all regular ties of subordination in

a condition of terminal decline, political anarchy was liable to resolve itself into

a military despotism. &States may, and they will best, exist with a partition of civil

powers', Burke is reported to have proclaimed. But, in stark contrast to this, &Armies

cannot exist under a divided command'. Where this division does obtain, we are

confronted with what amounts to &a state of war, or, at best, but a truce instead of

peace, in the country' [11].

In England in the 17th century, and even up to the 1750s, controversy had raged

over both the control of the militia and the permissibility of a permanent standing

army. Speaking to his peers in 1790, Burke was acutely conscious of the nature and

scope of this protracted controversy which had come to a crescendo after the Peace of

Ryswick between 1697 and 1699 (for a discussion, see [12]). But to him Article VI of

the Declaration of Right, establishing the requirement of parliamentary consent for

the maintenance of an army in peace-time, could be presented as having e!ectively

resolved the issue for good. From the perspective of a mounting crisis in France,

Old Whig and Tory opposition to a permanent military force retrospectively acquired

the status of a comparative tri#e: &We have', as Burke declared, &in such a

di$culty as that of "tting a standing army to the state2 done much better' [11,

p. 18]. But having &done much better', and remembering the &di$culty' experienced in

achieving this "t, Burke felt obliged to alert political opinion to the substantial threat

to the tranquillity of Europe posed by a major player in the power politics of the

continent whose military competence was being mobilised under conditions of

divided allegiance.

On one side of that divide, the doctrine of the &Rights of Man' stood ready to

eliminate spontaneous obedience as a legitimate principle of government. The successful

alignment of military force with executive and legislative power in Britain after

1688 had been part of a process in which, in Burke's words, &a revolution, [was] not

made, but prevented' [11, p. 20]. That process had involved at once the eviction of an

aspiring monarch and the restoration of a constitution. The constitutional settlement

had entrenched judicial independence and brought Britain's social ranks into harmony

with the organs of public power. It was that harmony which secured the state

against a military monarchy. Armed revolutionary doctrine in France, by contrast,

was proceeding to treat the state &like a country of conquest' [13]. From Burke's

point of view, the destructive intent of this conquest could be discovered in the

pronouncements made by leading members of the National Assembly. A declaration

made in 1789 by Rabaud de St. Etienne, a prominent member of the Constitutional

Committee, is cited by Burke as a case in point: & `Tous les e

H tablissemens en France

R. Bourke / History of European Ideas 25 (1999) 99}120 101

couronnent le malheur du peuple: pour le rendre heureux il faut le renouveler; changer

ses ideH es; changer ses loix; changer ses moeurs;2changer les hommes; changer les

choses; changer les mots2tout deH

truire; oui, tout deH

truire; puisque tout est a` recreH

er'''

[13, p. 216]. It is part of Burke's purpose in the Reyections to chart the probable stages

of this programme of &total destruction' leading to a military dictatorship.

In Burke's eyes, work on this programme had begun with the division and subdivision

of France into Departments, Communes and Cantons, out of which the

representation of the state was to be constructed by setting the size of the population

in a notionally proportionate relation to a contributory tax within each division.

By this process of political geometry, the French had embarked upon the destruction

of the bonds of their political union. Each Canton, Commune and Department,

electing deputies to their, respectively, superordinate bodies on the way to sending

representatives to the National Assembly, e!ectively constituted autonomous political

bodies within the state, cobbled together in haphazard fashion as a federal

association rather than a sovereign entity. &You cannot but perceive in this scheme',

Burke commented, &that it has a direct and immediate tendency to sever France

into a variety of republics, and to render them totally independent of each other,

without any direct constitutional means of coherence, connection, or subordination'

[13, p. 230].

Burke's analysis of the constitutional organisation of post-Revolutionary France is

signi"cantly indebted to Calonne's De l+e& tat de la France pre& sent et a% venir, published

in London in 1790. But his sense of the means necessary for holding the discrete

republican units comprising what had been the French monarchy together as a single

structure proceeded from his awareness of what to him was the evident constitutional

integrity of Britain. In France, with the interposition of two sets of magistracy between

the primary elective assemblies and the National Assembly itself, any meaningful

connection between constituents and the representatives of the state had been severed.

At the same time, deputies participating in the sovereign representative assembly

would inevitably see themselves as independent authorities acting as ambassadors

from nominally subordinate Departmental &states'.

France had been transformed into a loose confederation of units. In regard to

national power, the business of government and the system of representation had

become mutually incompatible. In regard to the people, representation itself was little

more than an impractical "ction. Substantive interests deriving from the primary

electoral base of the country could make no impact on the government of the territory

while an assortment of political bodies intervened between the constituencies and the

established public authority. At the same time, government itself could not function

while the state was being decomposed into discrete and competing sovereignties.

Surveying this morass of precipitous experimentation, Burke took some pleasure in

reminding his readers of the fact that &With us it is totally di!erent':

With us the representative, separated from the other parts, can have no action and

no existence. The government is the point of reference of the several members and

districts of our representation. This is the centre of our unity. This government of

reference is a trustee for the whole, and not for the parts [13, pp. 234}235].

102 R. Bourke / History of European Ideas 25 (1999) 99}120

But in France, now splintered into discordant pockets of power, coherence could

only be achieved by an unholy alliance between local oligarchies representing the

monied interest collaborating with the unchecked prerogatives concentrated in the

city of Paris.

These prerogative powers would open the way to a conquest of the country. The

National Assembly had successfully re-fashioned itself as a legislative and executive

power in the state freed of all judicial restraint. The king had been relegated to the

status of impotent notary while judicial independence had been happily aborted.

Military force would in the end become the "nal arbiter of all disputes fomented in the

various fragmentary districts currently presided over by what could only be described

as a legislative, judicial and executive tyranny. In theory there existed an independent

judiciary. But as things actually stood, judges chosen by popular election, and forced

to operate without reference to any established body of law, had little option but to

erect themselves into dispensers of an arbitrary justice. Moreover, beyond this,

a tribunal of justice in the hands of the state could override the competence of all

judicial administration. Justice was e!ectively in the hands of an unaccountable body

empowered to promulgate arbitrary decrees. Under the circumstances, Burke concluded,

control of the army would in due course become synonymous with control of

the state.

However, the "nal acquisition of control was situated on the far side of a bloody

struggle. At the point where democracy infected the structures of military command,

the disposition of the army would become &the true constitution of the state' [13,

p. 259]. Soldiers, on the evidence supplied by minister du Pin, were acting in de"ance

of all principles of seniority and obedience. But their de"ance would shortly be

compounded by the solution being o!ered with royal approval: the military were

instructed to join in their several corps with municipal clubs and confederations which

were themselves in the process of arrogating to themselves an authority over the

troops which theoretically belonged to the king. But of course it was precisely these

municipal assemblies which were set against the survival of royal authority.

Faced with this spectacle of constitutional chaos and military confusion, Burke

concluded that the &military lays open the civil, and the civil betrays the military

anarchy' [13, p. 263]. Civil society was collapsing into a mayhem of mutiny and

faction. Only time would redeem the wreckage. But even then, redemption would

scarcely come in a form conducive to constitutional liberty. It would come,

instead, when &some popular general, who understands the art of conciliating the

soldiery, and who possesses the true spirit of command, shall draw the eyes of all men

upon himself ' [13, p. 266]. Doubtless recalling to himself the English example of

Oliver Cromwell and the Roman example of Gaius Marius, as Adam Smith had

explicitly done in his Glasgow Lectures on jurisprudence of 1762, (see [14]) Burke

recounts the lesson to be drawn from the existence of a standing army in a popular

state, predicting that &the person who really commands the army' will emerge as &the

master2 of your king, the master of your assembly, the master of your whole

republic' [13, p. 266].

By 1796 the image of a military monarchy that would be created by the designs of

monied men in association with irreligious philosophes had been replaced by that of

R. Bourke / History of European Ideas 25 (1999) 99}120 103

2 The general problem of popular sovereignty is discussed extensively by I. Hont [16].

3On John Ball, fellow traveller of Wat Tyler and Jack Straw, preaching revolt against new taxes

introduced under Richard II: &One John Ball also, a seditious preacher, who a!ected low popularity, went

about the country and inculcated on his audience the principles of the "rst origin of mankind from one

common stock, their equal right to liberty and to all the goods of nature, the tyranny of arti"cial

distinctions, and the abuses which had arisen from the degradation of the more considerable parts of the

species, and the aggrandizement of a few insolent rulers. These doctrines, so agreeable to the populace, and

so comfortable to the ideas of primitive equality, which are engraven in the hearts of all men, were greedily

received by the multitude; and scattered the sparks of that sedition, which the present tax raised into

a con#agration'.

a conquering republic masterminded by men of letters in league with Machiavellian

politicians. These shady politicos who had seized the state in 1789 were held to be the

direct descendants of ambitious ministers lurking in the Court of Louis XV. As Burke

sets out his case in the Second Letter on a Regicide Peace, a secret cabal, armed with

Machiavelli's Discorsi and Montesquieu's Grandeur et de& cadence des Romains, and

disa!ected by their negligible political advance under Louis XIV, plotted to achieve

Universal Empire in Europe: &The di!erent e!ects of a great military and ambitious

republic, and of a monarchy of the same description were constantly in their mouths',

[15] and the comparison seduced them into preparing for the introduction of

a martial republic. It is clear that Burke's political intelligence is not most easily

discovered in the succession of conspiratorial alliances which appear in his writings on

France as the cause of the Revolution. What is impressive is his sense of the volatility

of a state struggling to come to terms with the unmanageable energy unleashed by its

attempt to give political e!ect to the principle of popular sovereignty.2 To him events

in France were explicable as a &Revolution of doctrine and theoretick dogma+ which, in

"nding political embodiment, resulted in civil war [17]. In endeavouring to transport

its doctrine beyond its frontiers, the French state threatened to awaken in Europe

factional hostilities more intense than any of its historic divisions*more intense than

those between Sparta and Athens, between the Guelfs and the Ghibillines, or between

Catholics and Protestants: &The treaty of Westphalia is, with France, an antiquated

fable' [17, p. 352].

Burke's assessment of the import of Revolutionary dogma is most carefully set out,

in 1791, in his Thoughts on French Awairs, where he takes Condorcet's ideas about

` &L'e

H galiteH naturelle des Hommes, et la SouverainteH du Peuple' a as encapsulating the

essential danger presented by Revolutionary ideology:

All former attempts grounded on these Rights of Men, had proved unfortunate. The

success of this last makes a mighty di!erence in the e!ect of the doctrine. Here is

a principle of a nature, to the multitude, the most seductive, always existing before

their eyes, as a thing feasible in practice [17, p. 371].

Burke had already cited the opinion of David Hume on the position of John Ball,

presented in The History of England, as `&conformable to the ideas of primitive

equality, which are engraven in the hearts of men' a [17, p. 369; 8, vol. II, pp. 289}290].3

104 R. Bourke / History of European Ideas 25 (1999) 99}120

Equality here entailed the absence of established subordination. It entailed an assertion

of natural liberty, and natural liberty amounted to a radical freedom to exercise

power: an &equal right', in Hume's sense, to dominion. &EgaliteH ' now meant each

person's easy empire over their own individual destinies in the world of human

circumstance and it was being held out &as a thing feasible in practice+. The &Souverainte

H du Peuple' carried with it the promise of realising the desire for glory secretly

&engraven in the hearts of all men'.

Two years after the publication of Thoughts on French Awairs, in the Observations on

the Conduct of the Minority, Burke came to elaborate on his earlier attempt to expose

the principle of popular sovereignty as it had been celebrated by Revolutionary

activists and originally formulated, we are now told, by Rousseau. To make his point,

Burke focuses on Titre III, article i, of the Constitution drawn up in 1791, condensed

into the following form: ` &La SouverainteH est une, indivisible, inalineable, et imprescriptible:

* Elle Appartient a la Nation: * Aucune Section du peuple, ni aucune

Individu ne peut s'en attribuer l'exercise' a [18]. The Observations was circulated by

Burke in 1793 in an e!ort to damage the political credibility of Charles James Fox in

the eyes of Whig grandees, principally the Duke of Portland and Earl Fitzwilliam. It

was, in other words, a bid to diminish the impact of putatively Jacobin principles

upon Burke's former political associates. The implication of the piece is that Fox too is

committed to a sovereignty &une, indivisible, inalienable, et imprescriptible+ residing in

the nation.

But in seeking to tarnish Fox's reputation, Burke signi"cantly rebuts the

claim embodied in the 1791 Constitution for its tendency to confound &in a

manner equally mischievous and stupid, the origin of a Government from the people

with its continuance in their hands' [18]. A multitude, Burke goes on

to argue, can scarcely be said to constitute a &people' prior to the establishment of the

state:

Before society, in a multitude of men, it is obvious, that sovereignty and subjection

are ideas which cannot exist. It is the compact on which society is formed that

makes both. But to suppose the people, contrary to their compacts, both to give

away and retain the same thing, is altogether absurd. It is worse, for it supposes in

any strong combination of men a power and right of always dissolving the social

union; which power, however, if it exists, renders them again as little sovereigns as

subjects, but a mere unconnected multitude [18, pp. 438}439].

To presuppose the existence of rights legitimately claimed by a collection of individuals

against an established sovereignty is to assume the viability of an ascendancy

of principle over the concrete reality of political power. In practice, this assumption

serves to vindicate the continuance in civil society of an equality of right which,

properly understood, de"nes the condition of natural liberty. Burke is here taking this

supposition to constitute the essence of Revolutionary ideology at its most dangerous:

it acts as an invitation to dissolve and recreate the &social union' at will. But the

invitation betrays a catastrophic disengagement from the circumstantial limitations

imposed upon human interaction by the demands of public authority. It betrays

R. Bourke / History of European Ideas 25 (1999) 99}120 105

4 &When the Parliament sat, that began in April 1640, and was dissolved in May following, and in which

many points of the regal power, which were necessary for the peace of the kingdom, and the safety of his

Majesty's person, were disputed and denied, Mr. Hobbes wrote a little treatise in English [i.e. The Elements

of Law], wherein he did set forth and demonstrate, that the said power and rights were inseparably annexed

to the sovereignty; which sovereignty they did not then deny to be in the King; but it seems understood not,

or would not understand that inseparability'.

5 For a discussion of Burke's attack on Revolutionary ideology as a resurgence of 17th-century

&enthusiasm', see [20]. &The defenders of religious and social structure in 18th-century Britain2 were

capable of identifying as enthusiasm any attempt to establish the reasoning mind's ascendancy over the

contexts in which it reasoned'.

6 For a discussion of Hobbes on rhetoric, see [21]. For the suggestion that Hobbes's thinking on the

subject decisively shifts between De Cive and Leviathan, see [22]. See also his somewhat earlier Thomas

Hobbes [23].

a preparedness to sacri"ce prudence to a set of political arrangements which are

rhetorically irresistible but practically redundant. The &theoretick dogma' which

de"ned the project of the Revolution amounted to a piece of destructive demagoguery

incapable of ful"lling the expectations it aroused.

3. Passion and prudence

In all this, Burke is re-tracing the argument supplied by Thomas Hobbes in 1640

against the &power and rights' then claimed by Parliament in opposition to the

&sovereignty' to which they were &inseparably annexed' (see [19]).4 What Burke

appreciated in Hobbes argument was his demonstration of the absurdity of pleading

liberty as an absolute right against an authority absolutely sovereign. The logical

absurdity anatomised in 1640 had become, in Burke's eyes, an anarchic reality in 1790.

This reality had made possible by the triumph of speculative enthusiasm over

practical wisdom,5 and Hobbes, once again, had diagnosed this condition in the

critical circumstances of the 1640s as deriving from the fatal predominance of

eloquence over reason.6

In the Elements of Law he informs his readership at a crucial stage in the argument

of the dangers which can proceed from the practice of deliberative oratory. These

dangers, however, are not to be understood as inherent in public speech per se

*oratio, after all, is only ratio become habit by the repeated &discourse of words' [24].

Instead they intervene at the point where speech commands agreement as a result of

"gurative enhancement rather than rigorous demonstration. But it is precisely "gurative

speech, or eloquence, which has the power to direct belief and, as such, is capable

of distorting an auditor's perception of moral qualities: by means of &aggravations and

extenuations' it can &make good and bad, right and wrong, appear great or less' [24, II,

viii, 14; pp. 140}141]. This aptitude for manipulation verges on recklessness where

persuasion is deployed in the absence of appropriate moderation. Moderation here is

106 R. Bourke / History of European Ideas 25 (1999) 99}120

7 The distinction between the two is drawn by Hobbes in [25]. &As, much Experience, is Prudence; so, is

much Science, Sapience. For though wee usually have one name of Wisdome for them both; yet the Latines

did alwayes distinguish between Prudentia and Sapientia; ascribing the former to Experience, the latter to

Science'. For clari"cation, see I, iii, 22: 'by how much one man has more experience of things past, than

another; by so much also he is more Prudent, and his expectations the seldomer faile him. The Present onely

has a being in Nature; things Past have a being in the Memory onely, but things to come have no being at all;

the Future being but a "ction of the mind, applying the sequels of actions Past, to actions that are

Present; which with most certainty is done by him that has most Experience; but not with certainty

enough. And though it be called Prudence, when the Event answereth our Expectation; yet in its own

nature, it is but Presumption' and compare with III, v, 35: &it appears that Reason is not as Sense, and

Memory, borne with us; nor gotten by Experience onely, as Prudence is; but attayned by Industry; "rst in

apt imposing of Names; and secondly by getting a good and orderly Method in proceeding from the

Elements, which are Names, to Assertions made by Connexion of one of them to another; and so to

Syllogismes, which are the Connexions of one Assertion to another; and that is it, me call SCIENCE. And

whereas Sense and Memory are but knowledge of Fact, which is a thing Past, and irrevocable; Science is the

knowledge of Consequences, and dependence of one Fact on another [2]'. But, of course, political science

must be brought to bear upon the world of human experience and will therefore be subject to the same

perilous vissicitudes as prudence.

8 The same point is made in T. Hobbes [26]. &Salust his Character of Catiline, (then whom there never was

a greater Artist in raising seditions) is this, That he had great eloquence, and little wisdome; he separates

wisdome from eloquence, attributing this as necessary to a man born for commotions, adjudging that as an

instructresse of Peace'.

9 Hobbes obviously had a fondness for the extended simile employed here which also appears in

Leviathan, II, xxx, 177a &And they that go about by disobedience, to doe no more than reforme the

Common-wealth, shall "nd they do thereby destroy it; like the foolish daughters of Peleus (in the Fable;)

which desiring to renew the youth of their decrepit Father, did by the Counsell of Medea, cut him in pieces,

and boyle him, together with strange herbs, but made not of him a new man'. The same fabular caveat

appears in Burke's Reyections as part of a general argument against reforming the state &by its subversion'.

See p. 146: &By this wise prejudice we are taught to look with horror on those children of their country who

are prompt rashly to hack that aged parent in pieces, and put him into the kettle of magicians, in hopes that

by their poisonous weeds, and wild incantations, they may regenerate the paternal constitution, and

renovate their father's life'.

supplied by either &prudence' or &sapience',7 by the appraisal of consequences, and

Hobbes's point is that the indulgence of oratory at the expense of these virtues is

a matter of serious concern where oratorical skill is marshalled by a seditious intent:

&It was noted by Sallust, that in Catiline (who was the author of the greatest sedition

Join now!

that ever was in Rome) there was Eloquenti~ satis, sapienti~ paruum; eloquence

su$cient, but little wisdom' [25, II, viii, 13; p. 139].8

It is Hobbes's purpose in The Elements of Law to diagnose the relation between

demagoguery and civil unrest. As part of that purpose, he is anxious to demonstrate

that the suspension of consequential reasoning allows "gurative speech to enjoy the

kind of freedom which can be prejudicial to public safety:

So when eloquence and want of judgement go together, want of judgement, like the

daughters of Pelias, consenteth, through eloquence, which is as the witchcraft of

Medea, to ...

This is a preview of the whole essay