Literature Review

Preface

        This literature review explores punishment in the society. Specifically, it explores the philosophical views of punishment, as well as the theoretical perspectives from the likes of Foucault, Bentham, Beccaria, Garland, Walker and others. First, explores early Greek philosophy of punishment up to Garland’s thesis of the relationship between punishment and culture. This literature review is descriptive and evaluative aiming to support the dissertation into full extent, basically to have an insight about the modern theories of punishment within the society.

Philosophical Views of Punishment

        There is no specific mark where people have started to realize the concept of punishment. However, its practice can be greatly reflected from ancient scriptures and from the words of ancient philosophers such as Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. For Aristotle, punishment is a paternal act, whereas the punisher exercises his power like a father to a child, or as a king to his subjects. As Aristotle stated “Thus, to be seen administering punishment paternally is to be seen acting like a king and for the benefit of the malefactor” (David, 1999). Socrates, on the other hand, accepted the notion that punishment is necessary “to serve as a corrective measure that would be of benefit to the criminal by helping him to overcome his evil tendencies” (Patterson, 1985, p.44). An opposite view was expressed by Crito, in which punishment “was to enable society to get even with the criminal by inflicting upon him an evil that was equivalent to the one he had caused others to suffer” (Patterson, 1985, p.44). Plato also believed that punishment is a necessary action for unjust actions of people. For Plato, men simply choose to be evil or to be good, where the former is punished and the latter rewarded. Punishment stands as form of lesson or consequence that the bad man will receive for his unjust actions (Thornburg, 2000).

        Modern philosophers have tried with great effort to explain what punishment is. Kant, in his book “The Science of Right”, asserted that to punish an offender is the sole right of the sovereign as the supreme power or the head of the state (Kant and Hastie, 1790, p.82). For Kant, the world would be without purpose if justice and righteousness would perish. Punishing the offender to whatever means is justice, given that it has been proven beyond reasonable doubt. Kant agrees that punishment is some kind of retribution for the offended that is executed by the authority to the offender. For Kant, the moment an individual does an unjust act; he already gives himself the right to be punished (Kant and Hastie, 1790, p.82; Barber, 1994). Kant firmly stated “In every punishment, as such, there must first be justice, and this constitutes the essence of the notion” (Kant, 1788, p.35), in the punisher must feel that justice is served and that the punished must feel that justice has been served unto him. In this sense, punishment is physical and mentally evil, but not necessarily morally evil (Kant, 1788, p.35).

On the other hand, for the early medieval philosopher Thomas Aquinas, the crime committed by a criminal is an offence to the whole community upholding such law against the crime committed. Thus, punishment is not revenge by the offended alone, but as payment to the debt of the criminal to the whole community. The criminal broke the law, and it is fitting that punishment must be served. Aquinas believes that punishment must be measured by the scale of the offender’s fault, not by the harm done. Punishment should only be for their offence. In other words, punishment should a matter of fairness, which is measured finding what is good for the whole community (Finnis, 1998). Aquinas also supported the notion that punishment should be for correcting the offender and not to seek revenge for the offended (Hanks, 1997). He mentioned that punishment should “…be corrective by being conducive either to the reform of the sinner or the good of society, which becomes more peaceful through the punishment of sinners" (Hanks, 1997, p.164).

Alternatively, the early medieval Augustine of Hippo had an opposite view about punishment. For Augustine, punishment should be retributive and deterrent, whereas capital punishment should be applied. Augustine justified capital punishment and stated: “He to whom authority is delegated, and who is but a sword in the hand of him who uses it, is not himself responsible for the death he deals” (St. Augustine, 1950). According to Augustine, the church and the state should be partners in governance, in which capital punishment should be applied in order to deter others to commit the same crime.

Modern Theories of Punishment

        Foucault’s view on the evolution of punishment contributes to its wealth of meaning and interpretation. In Discipline and Punish, Foucault (1977) explained the transformation in practices of punishment between the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, more specifically from “the spectacular reassertion of the power of the sovereign (public executions and torture as judgements of crime) to normalising detention (imprisonment as judgement of criminality)” (Glendinning, 1999, p.597). Foucault stresses that “punishment had not simply changed from being directed at the body to being directed at the mind; rather, both mind and body were now the objects of surveillance and disciplinary intervention” (Spierenburg, 2004, p.612). Foucault explained that these changes were caused by two factors: the spread of disciplinary techniques producing docile bodies; and the emergence of a government rationality dedicated to the welfare of the population of living, labouring and linguistic beings (Glendinning, 1999).

Join now!

Foucault adopted this idea from Bentham’s Panopticon (Glendinning, 1999).  Bentham’s view on punishment is utilitarian, which is greatly influenced by Beccaria’s philosophy of punishment (Draper, 2002). Cesare Beccaria, an Italian philosopher and criminologist in the 18th century started the idea that “punishment should fit the crime” (Latzer, 1998). For him, the true measure of crime is the injury done to the society (Latzer, 1998), a view that can be traced from Aquinas’s view of punishment. For him, legitimacy of punishment derives from contract and consent and human beings must, in principle, give their consent to being punished, which can be found ...

This is a preview of the whole essay