The phenomenological foundations of Sartrean Existentialism.

Authors Avatar

The phenomenological foundations of Sartrean Existentialism

April 7th 2003

A runt of a pink-feathered boa-wearing Frenchman, an iconoclast of a mid-20th century intellectual movement born out of the ashes of the Nietzschean Phoenix, and a prolific literary connoisseur all rolled into one, Jean Paul Sartre is the existentialist’ existentialist. In 1943 he published his chef-d'oeuvre- L’Etre et le Neant, an ontological analysis of human existence. Stretching out some 800 pages, this ambitious treatise of a new phenomenology is at first whiff obscure and verbose, unforgiving for the window shopping reader. Yet with a little background on phenomenological jargon, Sartre’s book is justified as an erudite attempt at a new philosophy for the human individual in the 20th century.         

Being born in France with philosophical aspirations, one was obliged to acknowledge the immortal French great Rene` Descartes (1596-1650). Descartes held an ideal of philosophy as a rigorous discipline, complete with all the certainty and infallibility of mathematics. For Descartes, the constant disagreement between philosophers was simply scandalous and disreputable. In formulating an indisputable, unshakable datum of philosophy within the warmth of his bread oven, Descartes concluded the immortal Latin phrase: Cogito ergo sum --I think, therefore I am.  For Sartre, as well as the other existentialists, it is compulsory to agree with Descartes that the primary object for philosophical reflection is man himself. In the novel Nausée, Sartre pays homage to Descartes:

“I jump up: it would be much better if I could only stop thinking. Thoughts are the dullest things… and they leave a funny taste in the mouth. Then there are words, inside the thoughts, unfinished words, a sketchy sentence, which constantly returns: ‘I have to fi… I ex… Dead… M. de Roll is dead … I am not … I ex…’ it goes, it goes… and there’s no end to it. It’s worse than the rest because I feel responsible and have complicity in it. For example this sort of painful rumination: I exist, I am the one who keeps it up. I… my thought is me: that’s why I can’t stop. I exist because I think … and I can’t stop myself from thinking.”

Sartre diverges from Descartes by not beginning his philosophy with a logical analysis of ideas but with a rude awakening to reality, minus a necessary reason for its existence and a stark depraved notion of absolute freedom.

In agreement with Descartes, Edmund Husserl thought that true philosophical reasoning ought to be scientific, yet far more rigorous than the sciences. However Husserl objected to the Cartesian implication of idealism and its inevitable solipsistic consequences, which is the assertion that phenomena are wholly mental, mind-dependent, and corruptible. Husserl thought that philosophy should be a ‘presuppositionless’ science that took nothing for granted. However, Husserl meant a science that was not in the spirit of mathematics or physics, nor a formation of inductive theories that explained phenomena, nor deducing conclusions from them either. In phenomenology one refuses to conjecture beyond the directly given in order to avoid error, and consequently the standard gridlocks in philosophy. There are no arguments in phenomenology; rather it is a descriptive method, it describes. Where do I find the roots of knowledge? “Wende zum Gegenstand!” The banner cry of phenomenology returns the locus of philosophy back to the objects, as they originally are present in the consciousness. The method reveals the objective structure or makeup of being instead of the structures of the mind because consciousness by its nature is consciousness of an object. Sartre, at this point, breaks off by disagreeing with Husserl’s phenomenological reduction as well as the notion of a transcendental ego. Sartre contends existence, not essence, is directly 'given' to consciousness. Existence, for Sartre, precedes or has priority over essence because existence is “the very paste of things.” 

Sartre’s precursor, Martin Heidegger was a student of Husserl. Heidegger was fascinated with the concept of time and called it the most important aspect of reality that it becomes ‘actual’ through man’s existence. Critics of L’Être who indicate that it is nothing more than a rip-off of Heidegger’s own pièce de résistance, Sein und Zeit, overlook the fact that Sartre focuses on the structures of consciousness, unlike Heidegger, who chooses to suppress the consciousness. According to Sartre, Heidegger could not be bothered about the ethical consequences of his version of existential phenomenology. Heidegger was instead preoccupied with the historical evolution of philosophy and the influences of history on the human consciousness. However a reading of L’Être et le Neant indicates that Sartre moves away from Husserl towards Heidegger, despite several differences.

To understand the introduction to L’Etre is to understand the entire book. Whosoever has already cut his teeth on Husserl and Heidegger will not find Sartre’s garrulous style intimidating. The main objective of the introduction is that Sartre intends to reveal that consciousness is in immediate contact with the existence of things. With a radical reinterpretation of phenomenology, Sartre disagrees with Husserl on two issues.

  • First Sartre shows that once Husserl attempts to replace the reality of the thing by its objectivity, he loses the unity of the existing thing. Husserl thought the most important feature of a thing was not its existence, but ‘what it is’ and by bracketing out the existent, universal essences where one could describe what the object was phenomenally.
  • Secondly, a grave dilemma arises when an infinite series of appearance supposedly guarantees the objectivity of the object. An object, say a coffee mug manifests exactly only one Abschattung- aspect- of itself to consciousness, yet Husserl asserts that the transcendental ego in a way unifies all the previous and following aspects into an ‘essence.’ An essence unifies the infinite number of appearances of an object- this spawns the problem of infinity within a finite object. Here Husserl is leaning towards dangerously back to the problem of dualism, which has plagued philosophy ever since Descartes introduced double substances.
Join now!

Sartre initially asks whether the ambition of “modern thought” has overcome the embarrassing problems of philosophy – dualism - and how successful have the phenomenologies of Husserl and Heidegger’s been in this respect. Sartre, in his haste to abandon the loose ends of dualism, underscores that at least it’s not the unattractive Kantian ‘ding-an-sich,’ the world of noumena; the true appearances of an object may be infinite in series, but the object itself is finite, limited. There may be infinite aspects of a coffee mug, but there is only one of it.

A new issue rears its head- the problem of ...

This is a preview of the whole essay