Immanuel Kant proposes a new science by which we would be able to examine and answer these questions. This science, transcendental idealism, finds as its focus the examination

Authors Avatar

McCarthy,

Karen McCarthy

Explication of Space

Thursday, September 29, 2005

        Any attempt to understand knowledge inevitably leads to a series of inquiries into the nature of those things that we know and their relationships to those means by which we purport to know of things.  Are there objects which are distinct from the thinker?  If there are external objects, how can the individual assure herself that her understanding of the world is accurate?  

        Immanuel Kant proposes a new science by which we would be able to examine and answer these questions.  This science, transcendental idealism, finds as its focus the examination of what must necessarily be so to account for the experiences that we have.  As part of his project, Kant looked to end the epistemological debate between the empiricists who held all knowledge to be dependant on direct experience and thus excluded any knowledge of abstract ideas, and the rationalists who allowed for innate knowledge of ideas far outside of the realm of experience.  

        Kant argues for a radical reassessment of the relationship between our knowledge and objects.  Rather than the traditional assumption that our ways of thought are determined by our experience with some inherent nature of things-in-themselves, Kant questions whether it may not be that our experiences with things are constructed by our ways of thought.  Through this revolution Kant builds a bridge between the opposing sides, allowing for some knowledge a priori (before experience).  He distinguishes between the noumenal world, which contains things-in-themselves and other transcendental ideas outside of experience, and the phenomenal world, which is the world as it appears to be and with which we can interact via experience.  We are capable of a priori knowledge solely with respect to how we organize the appearances of the phenomena.

        He identifies two components of our perceptions of appearances, sensibility and understanding.  It is by way of our sensibility that we are passively (inasmuch as we exert no influence over them) given those immediate perceptions (i.e. the sense of a color or texture or note), which are named by Kant intuitions.  Intuitions are then actively organized by concepts through the work of our understanding.  It is through the synthesis of intuitions and concepts that thinking occurs.

        Kant, in an effort to answer both contemporary empiricists and rationalists, finds that he must be able to account for judgments where the predicate is not simply just a part of the subject but in fact adds to the subject, and the whole judgment can be made a priori (synthetic a priori judgments).  It is in the first portion of his Critique of Pure Reason, “The Transcendental Doctrine of Elements,” that Kant addresses these a priori foundations of our experience.  He begins with the “Transcendental Aesthetic,” or those elements which must be presupposed if we are to have intuitions.

Join now!

        There are two types of intuitions. The matter, which is the correspondence between the object of perception and the sensations, is known to us only through experience (a posteriori), and is relatively uncontroversial.  The other type of intuition, the forms, is found in those intuitions which, as Kant asserts, must be present a priori to allow for an ordering of our sensations.  To find these necessary forms one must bracket out all contingent sense data.  When this is done those forms are found to be Space and Time.  Forms do not exist in themselves (there are no noumena which relate ...

This is a preview of the whole essay