Parliamentary Sovereignty

Authors Avatar

ACCORDING TO MARTIN LOUGHLIN, “SOVEREIGNTY DIVIDED IS SOVEREIGNTY DESTROYED” – DOES THIS ASSERTION MAKE SENSE IN THE LIGHT OF THE UK’S MEMBERSHIP OF THE EU?

‘A federal Europe does not mean the abolition of state sovereignty

itself, but its partial or total transference to a different level, deemed more capable of exercising it with efficacy.’

Introduction

A response to Loughlin’s claim is dependent on a comphrehensive analysis of a number of concepts and doctrines. Firstly, the unique character of the UK’s constitutional status, manifested in the sovereignty and supremacy of Parliament, provides the key areas of objection to the division of sovereignty and contributes to the assertion that it is somewhat destroyed by EU membership. However, Loughlin’s definition of sovererignty must also be examined in order to substantiate the argument that his particular reading of the concept fails to consider anything other than a juristic perpective, hence rendering it only partly useful. Therefore, specific cases dealt with by the European Court of Justice (ECJ) are investigated and conclusions are reached as whether the decisions made affect or even limit UK sovereignty. This analysis must take into account the different models of the European Union that can be presented and the dependence on specific policy areas in sovereignty definition exercises. 1951 saw the initial steps made towards European integration with the formation of the European Coal and Steel Community (ECSC) decided at the Treaty of Paris between the six founding states. This established a permanent bureaucracy and a legislative Council of Ministers. The expansion of the ECSC in 1957 at the Treaty of Rome into the European Economic Community called for extended political and judicial units – the European Court of Justice and the European Parliament. There are many conflicting arguments surrounding the condition of sovereignty in light of European integration. Whilst some claim that it no longer exists in its true and traditional form, others indicate a ‘pooling’ of sovereignty into a supranational body that removes some aspects of ultimate authority from the member-states. This essay recognises that UK entry into the EU did not intend to significantly alter the constitution. The evolutionary nature of development of the EU as an institution is perhaps most useful in examining the state of sovereignty and in supporting the conclusions that although clearly divided, sovereignty remains intact. In light of this, the doctrine also needs to evolve and can no longer be entreched in 19th century political philosophy.

Parliamentary Sovereignty

The historical development of the concept of sovereignty, and in particular the unique British model of Parliamentary Sovereignty, cannot be overlooked if a comprehensive investigation into the European model is going to occur. Internally, the UK retains a certain level of uniqueness in the creation of a distinct system that upholds the sovereignty of Parliament. Norton posits that the very specific Parliamentary response from the UK to European integration ‘can be explained in terms of constitutional, political and practical factors’.

That is, the historical facts of Parliament fighting bloodily to assert some authority over the monarch, resulting in the Glorious Revolution (1688) and the Bill of Rights (1689) which permanently affirmed the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty. The victory of Parliament in the battle against the crown as to who should wield ultimate authority caused this principle to be adopted and ‘judicially self-imposed’. Shortly afterwards, the Act of Settlement (1701) was mandated which, amongst other directives, gave judges independence from the crown. Britain is one of only three countries worldwide that possess an unwritten constitution and the flexibility that accompanies this results in the lack of any entrenchment provisions. The basis for the doctrine of Parliamentary sovereignty is undoubtedly A. V. Dicey’s (1835 – 1922) theories as explicated in ‘Introduction to the study of the Law of the Constitution’. The three key features of Parliamentary Sovereignty are as follows; firstly, a statute that is duly enacted by Parliament and in receipt of Royal Assent cannot be made invalid by any court. Secondly, Parliament is endowed with the authority to enact any law it wishes and is not bound by past legislatures nor binds those of the future. Finally, the doctrine stipulates that ‘no one person or body, other than Parliament itself, is recognised by the courts as having the right to override or set aside the legislation of Parliament’. However, it is important to note that, for Dicey, government consisted almost entirely of wealthy landowners and titled aristocrats who were not democratically elected. Courts purported theories of divine and natural law hence it is impossible to feasibly apply strict Dicean philosophy to a situation in which foreign courts influence domestic judges.

The prolific nature of this concept is closely linked with the growth of the modern European state system of autonomous nations. Sovereignty is manifested in two ways; internally and externally. In its most basic form, sovereignty was used to describe the overriding and supreme powers of a ruler, and later powers invested in affiliated institutions, within a state territory. Legally, this ‘internal coherence’ awards the sovereign ultimate authority and is therefore able to make, change and impose law on the citizens of that state. It is ‘primarily a matter of positive possession of ultimate power in a hierarchically structured internal legal framework’. The external manifestation of sovereignty is expressed quite differently, and it is the tension between the two that remains worthy of debate. Although states in the international arena remain independent and, formally, equal, the actual sovereignty of a state can never be fully understood in an international sense. Instead it is merely the description of a specific legal status that is valid in a specific legal jurisdiction and can therefore be realised as the ‘negative matter of denying the existence of an external sovereign authority’. International law reaffirms this position; it is an essential component of the United Nations Charter that the sovereignty and territorial integrity of a given state be recognised, explicitly stated in a declaration of International Law (Resolution 2625).

Join now!

The tradition notion of sovereignty does present a number of difficulties if attempts to understand it are made in a modern context. Firstly, the ‘external independence’ clause cannot be conceived fully within the construct of an international legal order. Its ‘internal coherence’ renders the state fully centralised, when in reality an increasing number of formerly unitary states are choosing to devolve and pluralise. Lastly, the tradition belief of a supreme and overriding authority awarded to the sovereign is hard to reconcile with a modern and democratic concept of transparency and accountability.

 

Loughlin’s definition of sovereignty

It ...

This is a preview of the whole essay