Are everyday causal judgements based on perceptions of empirical regularities or beliefs about causal powers?

Authors Avatar

Candidate Number: NO361, Student number: 000580650

Brain & Cognition PS3002

Assessed Essay, Ralph Gillett

19/3/03

Are everyday causal judgements based on perceptions of empirical regularities or beliefs about causal powers?

Our everyday judgements of the cause of events or happenings are intrinsically vital to every aspect of the theoretical and practical social sciences. Our question at hand is whether or not we can principally understand our judgements on the basis of the outcomes of previous similar experiences, or on our beliefs about the potentials of objects to be causal. Responsibility for our actions, and explaining the actions of unknown entities could be argued to be the very essence of human distinction from animals. The oldest of the enquiring disciplines of philosophy have wrangled with the notion of cause. For instance, White (1991) discusses how Aristotle’s understanding of the word ‘cause’ was discretely different to our modern use of the term – where the ‘cause’ is a larger concept than an immediate ‘reason’ for an event, but more towards a wider implication of a ‘purpose’ leading to a goal of development, or ‘telos’.

To sum up perhaps too simply, the enlightenment thinkers brought about a triumph of efficient causation and the abolition of final cause from scientific explanation (White, 1990). The conflicts of causal judgement concepts were played out between the figures of Mill and Hume. Mill, as Descartes and the classic philosophers before him, understood that:

“A statement of causation, is simply         a statement of necessary and sufficient conditions.”

(Skorupski, 1998: 204)

        This is important to remember when we do turn to our key contemporary theories on causal judgements, as the arguments inevitably encircle the extent to which Mill’s statement holds true. Lechalas said of Hume that:

        

        “[For Hume], the cause, or better still, the set of causes, is the totality of conditions preceding the predication of a phenomenon…”

(Mehlberg, 1980: 79)

        While Hume himself reflects that:

        “’Tis a general maxim of philosophy that whatever begins to exist, must have a cause of existence… but if we examine this maxim… on the contrary we shall find, that ‘tis of a nature quite foreign to that species of conviction”

(Hume, 1880/1958: 79)

In other words, philosophers of this era were well aware of their challenges to convention of ‘general maxims’, and of the paradoxes of tackling causality.

        This essay will attempt to review the prevalent psychological literature on the topic of causality but keeping Enlightenment rhetoric in mind, as ignoring the philosophical foundations of this long-contested debate would be foolhardy. Thus, we start with a common sense discussion of the double-edged question at hand: do we judge the cause of an event by the fact that something similar has happened before, or by the likelihood that the key objects involved have the tendency (‘power’) to be involved in the first place? These are over-simplifications on the subject of causality by Einhorn & Hogarth (1986) and White (1992) respectively.

Join now!

        The nature of all informed psychological literature is such that articles cannot disregard existing writing on a subject, so with each piece of research comes an increasingly-summarised review of the field. Einhorn & Hogarth (1986) begin by criticising theoretical views on causality:

        

        “Psychology is not alone in presenting a fragmented view of causality… In philosophy, the definition and meaning of cause have been debated for centuries.”

(Einhorn & Hogarth, 1986: 3)

Their theory is that empirical regularities, or ‘cues-to-causality’ are systematically employed by humans for ‘assessing cause, both in science and everyday inference’. The relatively recent ideas ...

This is a preview of the whole essay