Introduction

Aristotle's Politics is one of the most influential and enduring texts of political philosophy in all of history. The Aristotelian tradition has formed the backdrop against which all subsequent political and moral philosophy has found its orientation. While writers in the Aristotelian tradition believed that politics has to be based on a fundamental conception of the good as an objective ultimate end for human beings, political theorists from the pre-moderns to today have tried to base politics on anything but a shared idea of the good. The initial reason for this change is perhaps the fear that claiming the existence of one objective end for human life is too likely to lead to serious conflicts like the Wars of Religion.

These motivations are relatively clear at least in the case of Hobbes, who lived through both the Wars of Religion and the English Civil War, both of which were highly ideological conflicts, although concerns for power and material gain were also at the forefront. Hobbes attacks Aristotle vehemently in his writings, precisely because he is afraid that having such a clear-cut and universal conception of the good will inevitably lead to further ideological warfare. It is because the core assumptions of Hobbes' and Aristotle's thought are directly opposed to one another that Hobbes believes Aristotelian ideas sufficiently dangerous to merit such strong condemnation.

Furthermore, it may be a surprise to the reader that Marx, the father of communism, might have any connections to the democratic Ancient Greeks. Then it may be even more surprising to learn that Marx’s theories were at least partly based on and developed from Aristotle’s works on moral economy. There are many similarities between the works of Marx and Aristotle which help explain how Marx used Aristotelian philosophies as one of many bases for the development of communism. Aristotle wrote much on politics and political theory.

Different approaches, pessimistic and optimistic, can be taken in deciding whether humans are inherently evil or good and whether or not human beings are equal to one another. Ideas have spawned in the latter half of the second millennia from Thomas Hobbes and Karl Marx who each give their accounts of human nature in their works "The Leviathan" and "The Communist Manifesto".

In this paper, there will be an attempt to compare in a political-philosophical perspective the ideas of Aristotle, Hobbes and Marx.

Aristotle and Hobbes

While Hobbes constantly emphasizes the absolute necessity of acting rationally for self-preservation, Aristotle looks beyond the mere goal of living to the higher aim of living well, in accordance with the natural function of man. This emphasis on living well is a danger in Hobbes' view, for he believes that any lofty ideals for which one may be willing to sacrifice one's life can lead to rebellion and the dissolution of the commonwealth. From Aristotle's perspective, what Hobbes fails to understand is that the goal of self-preservation will not suffice to motivate people to moderate their desires and restrain their actions. Hobbes, however, a skeptic who had been highly influenced by the writings of Descartes, simply did not believe in the existence of an ultimate good, or even for that matter in the existence of objective reality outside the human mind.

Join now!

Hobbes rejects the teleology of Aristotelian science. His view of man is shaped by Galileo's new insights about motion. His translation of the revolutionary doctrines of physics into claims about man and politics is a most remarkable piece of creative thinking. Life is not aimed at the attainment of the mature state of the species as Aristotle claimed. Man, like other physical objects, keeps moving until something (death, in the case of man) stops him. Yet the reaction to Aristotle and scholasticism was not a matter of simply rejecting the philosophy of Aristotle wholesale. The relation whom philosophers had ...

This is a preview of the whole essay